25.12.2012 Views

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

Willard Van Orman Quine

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

44 robert j. fogelin<br />

I got into the conversation, and the exchange continued as follows:<br />

Fogelin: Is it fair to say that your answer is grounded in a kind of theory of<br />

inquiry...[atheory of] what honest inquiry looks like?<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>: Very good, yes.<br />

Fogelin: And these [Cartesian] doubts simply don’t have a place in honest<br />

inquiry?<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>: Yes. 14<br />

<strong>Quine</strong>’s refusal to be concerned with problems that are not empirically<br />

motivated emerged again with his quick dismissal of the brainin-the-vat<br />

problem.<br />

My attitude toward [this] is the same as my attitude toward more commonplace<br />

situations where the thing is not quite so unthinkable from a naïve<br />

point of view. Namely, I would think in terms of naturalistic plausibility.<br />

What we know, or what we firmly believe,...is that it would really be an<br />

implausible achievement, at this stage anyway, to rig up such a brain. And<br />

so I don’t think I am one [i.e., a brain in a vat]. 15<br />

The clear implication of this passage is that naturalized epistemologists,<br />

like scientists generally, will only concern themselves with<br />

matters having a suitably high degree of “naturalistic plausibility.”<br />

It is, of course, entirely possible that with the advance of technology<br />

brains could be rigged up in the way envisaged in skeptical scenarios.<br />

They might be featured in science museums. In that world, <strong>Quine</strong>’s<br />

response would be inadequate. And there is some chance that we are<br />

in such a world. <strong>Quine</strong> would not have denied this. Furthermore, he<br />

did not, as others have, attempt to find some purely conceptual argument<br />

(or transcendental argument) intended to rule this possibility<br />

out. Such arguments have no place in the naturalized epistemological<br />

arsenal.<br />

But, alas, <strong>Quine</strong> was not always as fully committed to a naturalistic<br />

standpoint as he might have been. This comes out in two ways.<br />

First, in the development of his own views he tended to move at<br />

a very high level of theoretical generality, rarely touching down at<br />

empirical checkpoints. He often seemed more concerned with the relationship<br />

between his philosophical position and the philosophical<br />

positions of others than with the relationship between his position<br />

and the data needed to support it. As a result, contrary to <strong>Quine</strong>’s<br />

stated intentions, his theory sometimes looks more like an “a priori<br />

Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!