25.10.2012 Views

Laurie Bauer - WordPress.com — Get a Free Blog Here

Laurie Bauer - WordPress.com — Get a Free Blog Here

Laurie Bauer - WordPress.com — Get a Free Blog Here

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE LINGUISTICS STUDENT’S HANDBOOK 52<br />

refuted, e.g. by Gazdar et al. (1985), but was generally accepted for many years.<br />

It seemed, however, that separate rules would be required to move constituents<br />

in pairs like (5) and (6) if the relationships holding between these pairs was to<br />

be recognised by the grammar. These movement rules are different in type<br />

from the phrase-structure rules (also known as rewrite rules), and are called<br />

transformational rules. The form and nature of movement rules have<br />

changed considerably over the various versions of Chomskyan grammar, but<br />

we still have an underlying order of elements created by phrase-structure rules,<br />

and transformational or movement rules which produce the actually occurring<br />

sentence structure. The underlying order of elements was originally called<br />

deep structure, and the observable output of the full set of rules was called<br />

the surface structure. The term deep structure was often used informally to<br />

mean any level more abstract than the actually occurring surface form. In later<br />

versions this was reformulated in terms of D-structure and S-structure, where<br />

D-structure is equivalent to deep structure, but S-structure differs from<br />

surface structure. Surface structure is the immediate input into the rules<br />

which provide a pronunciation of the sentence under consideration, while Sstructure<br />

is the input to the semantic <strong>com</strong>ponent, and still contains some<br />

empty elements such as traces, which are not pronounced at all.<br />

(5) a. I can put up Kim<br />

b. I can put Kim up.<br />

(6) a. I can’t stand olives.<br />

b. Olives, I can’t stand.<br />

The evaluation of grammars<br />

According to Chomsky (1964), grammars can hope to achieve one of three<br />

levels of adequacy. A grammar that is observationally adequate contains<br />

sufficient information to reproduce just the data on which it is based. A<br />

grammar is descriptively adequate if it contains sufficient information not<br />

only to account for the input data, but to assign a structure which reflects precisely<br />

those patterns in the data that are captured by the intuitions of the native<br />

speaker. Finally, a grammar is explanatorily adequate if it derives from a linguistic<br />

theory which allows the selection of the best possible descriptively adequate<br />

grammar from those which are <strong>com</strong>patible with the data. Chomsky has<br />

consistently sought explanatory adequacy. However we may phrase this<br />

requirement, what it translates as is a push to find out why particular patterns<br />

should occur in individual languages, why languages should differ in the<br />

observed patterns, and what fundamental principles govern the kinds of<br />

pattern that are observed. Examples are provided by the pairs in (7) and (8),<br />

where one language allows a pattern which a neighbouring language does not

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!