15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

116 <strong>Theism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Explanation</strong><br />

the insight that this is how we actually choose theories. Nor does it show<br />

that we are acting irrationally in doing so.<br />

Since there exists no defi nite or exhaustive list of explana<strong>to</strong>ry virtues, we<br />

are forced <strong>to</strong> choose which we shall adopt. Here is my choice. A potential<br />

explanation of some fact can be regarded as its best explanation if it possesses<br />

the following features. Our preferred theory will have a high degree<br />

of testability; indeed, it will have survived independent tests. It will posit<br />

mechanisms that are at least analogous <strong>to</strong> those with which we are already<br />

familiar, <strong>and</strong> will form part of a previously successful research tradition.<br />

It will also be simple, on<strong>to</strong>logically economical, <strong>and</strong> informative. There is<br />

nothing particularly authoritative about this list. The features it names are<br />

closely related, <strong>and</strong> it may be that with a bit of reworking the number could<br />

be reduced <strong>to</strong> three or four. And more desiderata could perhaps be added.<br />

The fecundity of a theory—its ability <strong>to</strong> suggest new lines of research—<br />

would be one obvious addition. But one has <strong>to</strong> s<strong>to</strong>p somewhere. I have<br />

chosen this particular set of virtues for reasons of convenience, <strong>and</strong> because<br />

most lists of explana<strong>to</strong>ry virtues will include desiderata that include or at<br />

least resemble those given here. If a proposed theistic explanation were <strong>to</strong><br />

rate poorly, when measured against these criteria, this would be a suffi cient<br />

reason <strong>to</strong> seek a natural alternative.<br />

7.1 TESTABILITY<br />

My fi rst desideratum in a hypothesis worthy of our acceptance is that it<br />

should be testable. Indeed many philosophers <strong>and</strong> scientists have regarded<br />

testability as the distinguishing mark of the sciences (<strong>and</strong> a lack of testability<br />

as the mark of a pseudo-science). In this sense, they regard testability as<br />

a necessary condition of at least a scientifi c explanation. For Carl Hempel,<br />

for instance, the “methodological unity of the sciences” consists in precisely<br />

this: that their theories are testable.<br />

Notwithst<strong>and</strong>ing many differences in their techniques of investigation,<br />

all branches of empirical science test <strong>and</strong> support their statements in<br />

basically the same manner, namely, by deriving from them implications<br />

that can be checked intersubjectively <strong>and</strong> by performing for those implications<br />

the appropriate experimental or observational tests. 3<br />

Of course, testability, by itself, does not take us very far. Many theories<br />

remain testable that are now entirely discredited; indeed they were discredited<br />

precisely because they were testable (<strong>and</strong> have failed the test). As Frank<br />

Cioffi writes, “the propensity <strong>to</strong> melancholy of those born under Saturn” or<br />

“the immunity <strong>to</strong> appendicitis of people ignorant of the vermiform appendix”<br />

are both eminently testable hypotheses. 4 But they are not for that reason

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!