15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

30 <strong>Theism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Explanation</strong><br />

(3.2.3.1). For the moment, I wish merely <strong>to</strong> ask what kind of an objection<br />

it is. If we employ the distinction I have just outlined, this argument<br />

counts as a de fac<strong>to</strong> objection <strong>to</strong> theistic explanations. For even if any event<br />

could be substituted for E—which, incidentally, I don’t believe <strong>to</strong> be true<br />

(3.2.3.1)—H would still be a potential explanation of E. One could use H<br />

<strong>to</strong> construct an argument that corresponds <strong>to</strong> the second premise of Peirce’s<br />

schema, albeit in an almost trivial fashion.<br />

(1) God wills E.<br />

(2) Whatever God wills comes about.<br />

(3) Therefore E.<br />

But, of course, “God wills E” will still fail <strong>to</strong> count as an actual explanation.<br />

Why? Because it would have practically no empirical content (3.2.3)<br />

<strong>and</strong> would not be independently testable (7.1).<br />

The point I am making here is that, on my terms, the above objection<br />

is a de fac<strong>to</strong> objection, not an in principle one. This may seem odd. I can<br />

imagine someone else regarding it as an in principle objection; some of the<br />

authors cited above seem <strong>to</strong> have done so. But the problem here is largely<br />

terminological. My distinction is not the only one that could be adopted in<br />

such discussions. But I have <strong>to</strong> start somewhere, <strong>and</strong> this is the distinction<br />

I shall use in the discussion that follows.<br />

2.2.2 The Way Ahead<br />

The distinctions I have made will determine the shape of the discussion <strong>to</strong><br />

come. Chapters 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 are largely descriptive, setting out as clearly as possible<br />

just what I mean by a proposed theistic explanation. Chapter 3 will<br />

take as its starting point the explanans of such a proposed explanation. It<br />

will argue that a theistic explanation is a theoretical explanation, positing<br />

a particular divine intention, <strong>and</strong> embodying a causal claim. In the course<br />

of the discussion, I shall examine two initial objections <strong>to</strong> the very idea of<br />

such an explanation. The fi rst is that the idea of a divine agent is internally<br />

inconsistent. The second is the related claim that the will of God cannot be<br />

described as a cause. Neither objection, I shall argue, is necessarily fatal,<br />

although both imply that the theist has some work <strong>to</strong> do.<br />

Chapter 4 will continue my description of theistic explanations, but from<br />

the point of view of their explan<strong>and</strong>a. I shall argue that theistic explanations<br />

cover both events <strong>and</strong> states of affairs <strong>and</strong> that they embody both<br />

singular <strong>and</strong> general causal claims. I shall then examine the relationship<br />

between theistic <strong>and</strong> secular explanations, highlighting the fact that the<br />

two forms of explanation can, on occasions, be complementary. This will<br />

bring me <strong>to</strong> a third objection <strong>to</strong> such proposed explanations, which has <strong>to</strong><br />

do with miracles. At least some theistic explanations posit miracles. And<br />

all theistic explanations posit an agent capable of working miracles. But

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!