15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

80 <strong>Theism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Explanation</strong><br />

low—that the facts we observe are extremely unlikely <strong>to</strong> have occurred by<br />

chance. We also need <strong>to</strong> show that the likelihood that we should observe<br />

the same facts is higher, given design. And <strong>to</strong> do this, we need <strong>to</strong> be able <strong>to</strong><br />

predict what would follow if the hypothesis were true.<br />

I shall look at Sober’s claim that proposed explanations cannot win by<br />

default later (7.1.3). I think it is true (6.2.2), although I am not convinced by<br />

the particular arguments he offers. But his underlying point seems uncontroversial.<br />

If we are <strong>to</strong> take a proposed explanation seriously, we must be<br />

able <strong>to</strong> predict what would follow if it were true. Sober’s argument is that in<br />

the case of a proposed theistic explanation this condition cannot be fulfi lled.<br />

He formulates his objection in terms of testability: if one cannot say what<br />

would (<strong>and</strong> would not) follow if a hypothesis were true, then that hypothesis<br />

is untestable. But there is a prior <strong>and</strong> more important question. If Sober<br />

is correct, the problem is not merely that the proposed theistic explanation<br />

is not testable; we cannot know that it is even a potential explanation of the<br />

fact in question. A potential explanation, I have argued (2.1.2), is one that<br />

satisfi es the second premise of Peirce’s abductive schema.<br />

(1) The surprising fact, E, is observed.<br />

(2) But if H were true, E would be a matter of course.<br />

(3) Hence, there is reason <strong>to</strong> suspect that H is true.<br />

If we cannot know what would follow, given the truth of a theistic hypothesis,<br />

then we cannot say whether it meets this condition. We do not know if<br />

the explan<strong>and</strong>um is what we would expect, given the truth of the explanans.<br />

If this were true, it would constitute a strong in principle objection <strong>to</strong><br />

all proposed explanations of this kind.<br />

So on what grounds does Sober argue in support of what I am calling<br />

“theological scepticism”? He argues that theists simply cannot specify how<br />

their posited designer would be expected <strong>to</strong> act, in order <strong>to</strong> achieve his<br />

goals. Why? Because <strong>to</strong> do so, writes Sober, would require<br />

further assumptions about what the designer’s goals <strong>and</strong> abilities would<br />

be, if he existed. Perhaps the designer would never build the vertebrate<br />

eye [for example] with features F 1 . . . F n either because he would lack<br />

the goals or would lack the ability. If so, the likelihood of the design hypothesis<br />

is zero. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, perhaps the designer would want<br />

<strong>to</strong> build the eye with features F 1 . . . F n <strong>and</strong> would be entirely competent<br />

<strong>to</strong> bring this plan <strong>to</strong> fruition. If so, the likelihood of the design hypothesis<br />

is unity. There are as many likelihoods as there are suppositions<br />

concerning the goals <strong>and</strong> abilities of the putative designer. Which of<br />

these, or which class of these, should we take seriously? 6<br />

It is true, Sober concedes, that we can identify the products of human<br />

design. But we can do so only because we know something of the goals <strong>and</strong>

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!