15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

What are Theistic <strong>Explanation</strong>s? 55<br />

effi cacious cause is <strong>to</strong> reject the theistic hypothesis. For as we have seen,<br />

God’s willing of an event or state of affairs cannot be other than unfailingly<br />

effi cacious. It is unthinkable that God would will e <strong>and</strong> that e would not<br />

occur. And it is unthinkable that God, the divine cause, could be dependent,<br />

even counterfactually, on what he himself creates. It follows that the<br />

counterfactual analysis of causation is not applicable <strong>to</strong> God. It cannot<br />

avoid the “spurious causal dependence” problem identifi ed by Lewis.<br />

3.4.3.2 An In Principle Argument<br />

These refl ections bring Smith <strong>to</strong> his second, in principle, argument against<br />

the idea of divine causation. It relies on the idea that if an event or state, x,<br />

is a logically suffi cient condition of another event or state, y, then x cannot<br />

also be the cause of y. To take Smith’s example, “a body’s being in motion<br />

is logically suffi cient condition of the body occupying space.” 95 So far, so<br />

good, although this surely needs rewording. If the condition in question is<br />

logical, it seems better <strong>to</strong> express it as a relationship between propositions.<br />

The truth of the proposition “the body is in motion” is a logically suffi cient<br />

condition of the truth of the proposition “the body occupies space.” For if<br />

a body is in motion, it must also be in space, <strong>and</strong> we could underst<strong>and</strong> this<br />

from an analysis of both concepts. Nonetheless, Smith argues, “the body’s<br />

being in motion is not the cause of the body’s occupation of space.” 96 This,<br />

<strong>to</strong>o, seems correct. Intuitively, at least, we would not speak of this as a<br />

cause. This gives us, in Smith’s view, a distinction between logically suffi<br />

cient conditions <strong>and</strong> causes.<br />

In<strong>to</strong> which category does the action of God fall? Smith argues that God’s<br />

willing y is a logically suffi cient condition of y. Again, we might more accurately<br />

express this in terms of propositions. Where y is any event, the truth<br />

of “God wills y” is a logically suffi cient condition of “y occurs.” For if an<br />

omnipotent being wills y <strong>and</strong> y does not occur, then the agent in question<br />

is not an omnipotent being. But this is a contradiction. Given the principle<br />

that a logically suffi cient condition cannot be a cause, it follows that God’s<br />

willing y cannot be a cause of y. Smith speaks of a cause of the universe, but<br />

it seems it would be true whatever we substitute for y.<br />

If this argument is sound, it is a fatal objection <strong>to</strong> the very idea of a<br />

theistic explanation. For it entails that any argument which suggests that<br />

x—let’s say the universe—has a cause is also an argument against the idea<br />

that its cause is a divine state. And on the assumption that all explanations<br />

are causal explanations, then there could never be a successful theistic<br />

explanation. How might the defender of theistic explanations respond?<br />

Are all explanations causal? One response would be <strong>to</strong> deny the assumption:<br />

the idea that all explanations are causal explanations. The theist might<br />

argue that while all scientifi c explanations might be causal explanations,<br />

when science runs out, theology takes over. And what theology offers is a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!