15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Potential Theistic <strong>Explanation</strong>s 85<br />

by no other agent. First of all, he is assumed <strong>to</strong> be omniscient. This means<br />

that his beliefs simply mirror the way the world is: for any proposition<br />

p, “if p, God knows that p.” 21 Secondly, he is assumed <strong>to</strong> be omnipotent.<br />

This means that there are no constraints on how he might realise his intentions,<br />

other than those of logical possibility. If a consistent description can<br />

be given of an action, then God can perform it. Thirdly, he is thought <strong>to</strong><br />

be morally perfect. At the very least, I shall argue, this means that God<br />

will seek <strong>to</strong> minimise suffering. So the key question is: What would be the<br />

most rational way in which an omnipotent, omniscient, <strong>and</strong> morally perfect<br />

agent could bring about his intended goal?<br />

5.3.1 The Divine Agent<br />

Given the nature of the posited divine agent, there are a number of fac<strong>to</strong>rs<br />

that shape human action which we can exclude from the outset. Firstly, it<br />

cannot be the case that God acts on the basis of false beliefs or on the basis<br />

of unconscious or only partly recognised desires. As an omniscient agent,<br />

God has no false beliefs or unrecognised desires. Secondly, it cannot be the<br />

case that God is constrained in his choice of means <strong>to</strong>wards an end. As an<br />

omnipotent agent, God acts under no constraints, other than that of the<br />

logically possible, which is really no constraint at all. Thirdly, God cannot<br />

suffer from weakness of will (akrasia). It is inconceivable that he should<br />

will an action, but because of his own weakness fail <strong>to</strong> bring it about. As<br />

we have seen (3.4.2), the divine will is unfailingly effi cacious. Fourthly,<br />

God cannot be under any compulsion <strong>to</strong> adopt any means <strong>to</strong>wards an end.<br />

He could bring about whatever he wills merely by willing it: if he chose,<br />

all of his actions could be basic actions (3.4.2). God could create a world<br />

as directly as I move my arm. 22 But if God is morally perfect, has no false<br />

beliefs, <strong>and</strong> suffers no constraints on his action, what follows? On the<br />

assumption that he is rational agent we can assume whatever he wills, he<br />

would choose the best possible means of achieving it. I shall refer <strong>to</strong> this<br />

as the optimality condition <strong>and</strong> shall argue that it is the most important<br />

constraint on a proposed theistic explanation.<br />

5.3.2 Suboptimality Arguments<br />

What the optimality condition offers is something very important: a test of<br />

whether a proposed theistic explanation is even a potential explanation of<br />

the fact <strong>to</strong> be explained. The key question is: Given the posited divine goal,<br />

is the explan<strong>and</strong>um the best way in which this goal could be realised? If<br />

not, then we cannot plausibly attribute it <strong>to</strong> God. It is true that I still need<br />

<strong>to</strong> show that we can answer the question. Perhaps there is no “best means”<br />

of achieving some goal, or perhaps we cannot know what it is. I shall come<br />

<strong>to</strong> these objections in a moment (5.4). But before I do so, let me spell out my<br />

argument a little more clearly.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!