15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

178 Notes<br />

43. Swinburne, Existence of God, 165, 185.<br />

44. Shanks, God, the Devil, <strong>and</strong> Darwin, 219.<br />

45. Hume, “Enquiry,” §90 (114). His fuller defi nition is, “a transgression of a<br />

law of nature by a particular volition of the Deity, or by the interposition of<br />

some invisible agent” (ibid., 115 n. 1).<br />

46. An assumption that is (as I noted earlier) no longer uncontested (Steinhardt<br />

<strong>and</strong> Turok, “A Cyclic Model of the Universe,” 1436–39).<br />

47. You might argue, as does William Lane Craig (in Craig <strong>and</strong> Smith, <strong>Theism</strong>,<br />

Atheism, <strong>and</strong> Big Bang Cosmology, 231), that a natural explanation<br />

of the beginning of the universe violates the principle ex nihilo nihil fi t. But,<br />

as Craig recognises, this is a metaphysical principle rather than a law of<br />

nature.<br />

48. Craig, “Problem of Miracles,” 29.<br />

49. Quentin Smith (“The Reason the Universe Exists,” 579–86) argues that the<br />

universe could have caused itself <strong>to</strong> begin <strong>to</strong> exist. I am not (yet) convinced,<br />

but I shall not address his arguments here.<br />

50. Smith, “His<strong>to</strong>rical Method,” 7.<br />

51. Pennock, Tower of Babel, 194–5.<br />

52. Strauss, The Life of Jesus, §14 (79).<br />

53. You might, for instance, expect such a being <strong>to</strong> create the world, as he wanted<br />

it <strong>to</strong> be, by a single divine act, merely by willing it in<strong>to</strong> existence. But you<br />

might not expect that such a world would require his ongoing miraculous<br />

intervention. (On the latter point, see Quentin Smith’s argument in Craig <strong>and</strong><br />

Smith, <strong>Theism</strong>, Atheism, <strong>and</strong> Big Bang Cosmology, 202–6.)<br />

54. It is true that Hume’s argument applies primarily <strong>to</strong> his<strong>to</strong>rical reports of<br />

miracles, but I take it <strong>to</strong> be applicable even <strong>to</strong> those events which we witness<br />

fi rst-h<strong>and</strong>.<br />

55. Hume, “Enquiry,” §86 (110).<br />

56. Ibid., §90 (115).<br />

57. Earman, “Bayes, Hume, <strong>and</strong> Miracles,” 297.<br />

NOTES TO CHAPTER 5<br />

1. Earman, Hume’s Abject Failure, 3.<br />

2. Hume, “Dialogues,” xi (107).<br />

3. Hume, “Enquiry,” §57 (72).<br />

4. Sober, “Design Argument,” 28–29.<br />

5. See, for instance, Dembski, “Obsessively Criticized,” Section 4.<br />

6. Sober, “Design Argument,” 38.<br />

7. Sober, “Testability,” 64; “Design Argument,” 39.<br />

8. Sober, “Design Argument,” 38.<br />

9. Sober, “Testability,” 65.<br />

10. Sober, “Probability Reasoning,” 75.<br />

11. Ibid. .<br />

12. Kitcher, “Explana<strong>to</strong>ry Unifi cation,” 528.<br />

13. Sober, “Testability,” 65; “Intelligent Design,” 76; “Design Argument,”<br />

41–42.<br />

14. This is not identical with the criterion of independent specifi cation sometimes<br />

employed in discussions of causation—the idea that “A cannot be regarded as<br />

a cause of B unless A can be specifi ed in some way that does not mention B”<br />

(Pears, “Desires as Causes,” 86). As David Pears argues (ibid., 86–87), this<br />

principle is far from fi rmly established. But it is a different principle from the<br />

one I am defending here.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!