15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Successful Theistic <strong>Explanation</strong>s 133<br />

Swinburne adopts what we may call a “metaphysical” conception of simplicity.<br />

68 The simplicity of a theory, he writes,<br />

is a matter of its postulating few (logically independent) entities, few<br />

properties of entities, few kinds of entities, few kinds of properties,<br />

properties more readily observable, few separate laws with few terms<br />

relating few variables, the simplest formulation of each law being mathematically<br />

simple. 69<br />

This is a very broad defi nition indeed, <strong>and</strong> its application <strong>to</strong> theism is problematic.<br />

70 Is God really, as Swinburne argues, “the simplest kind of person<br />

there could be?” 71 As we have seen (3.3.1), there does exist a theistic doctrine<br />

of divine simplicity, which in some form or other Swinburne wishes<br />

<strong>to</strong> endorse. 72 But one could argue, with Cleanthes (<strong>and</strong> Plantinga), 73 that<br />

this doctrine is incompatible with the idea that God is a personal agent.<br />

And what about the doctrine of the Trinitarian nature of God? Is this compatible<br />

with the idea that God is “the simplest kind of person there is?” 74<br />

Perhaps it is, but the theist at least has a case <strong>to</strong> answer here.<br />

7.4.1 Auxiliary Hypotheses<br />

Swinburne’s criterion of simplicity is closely related <strong>to</strong> what I shall call<br />

“on<strong>to</strong>logical economy,” <strong>and</strong> which I shall discuss in a moment (7.5). I favour<br />

a rather different defi nition of simplicity, which is broadly Popperian in fl avour<br />

<strong>and</strong> which is most clearly expressed in the work of Paul Thagard. Karl<br />

Popper offers what at fi rst sight seems an idiosyncratic defi nition of simplicity.<br />

The simplicity of a theory, he suggests, is equivalent <strong>to</strong> its empirical<br />

content or degree of falsifi ability. 75 Building on this foundation, Thagard<br />

argues that simplicity has <strong>to</strong> do with the number of auxiliary hypotheses<br />

that a theory requires in order <strong>to</strong> explain the fact in question. The fewer the<br />

auxiliary hypotheses, the simpler the theory.<br />

Note how Thagard’s conception of simplicity differs from Swinburne’s.<br />

Thagard does not argue that one theory (T 1 ) should be preferred <strong>to</strong> another<br />

(T 2 ) simply because T 1 postulates the existence of fewer entities. In fact,<br />

he argues that we may prefer a theory that postulates more entities than<br />

its competi<strong>to</strong>rs if it has greater explana<strong>to</strong>ry power or, in Thagard’s terms,<br />

if it contributes <strong>to</strong> consilience. 76 The important fact—that which makes a<br />

theory simple in Thagard’s sense—is that it contributes <strong>to</strong>wards consilience<br />

“without making a host of assumptions with narrow application.” 77<br />

At fi rst sight, Thagard’s conception of simplicity may seem different<br />

from Popper’s, but in fact the two are closely related. For a theory that is<br />

preserved from refutation only with the aid of auxiliary hypotheses loses<br />

empirical content. It is, in Popper’s terms, less falsifi able <strong>and</strong> <strong>to</strong> this extent<br />

more complex. 78 This account of simplicity, as developed by Thagard, seems<br />

more workable than Swinburne’s conception, which requires us <strong>to</strong> count<br />

the number of entities or principles a theory employs. Any such count will

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!