15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

5 Potential Theistic <strong>Explanation</strong>s<br />

What a book a devil’s chaplain might write on the clumsy, wasteful,<br />

blundering, low, <strong>and</strong> horribly cruel works of nature.<br />

Charles Darwin<br />

In my opening chapter (1.3), I distinguished between potential <strong>and</strong> actual<br />

(or successful) explanations. I suggested that I needed this distinction—or<br />

something like it—in order <strong>to</strong> distinguish between de fac<strong>to</strong> <strong>and</strong> in principle<br />

objections <strong>to</strong> proposed theistic explanations. A de fac<strong>to</strong> objection accepts<br />

that some accounts of divine action are potential explanations. If they were<br />

true, then the explan<strong>and</strong>um is what we would expect. But it argues that<br />

such proposed explanations have been superseded by secular alternatives,<br />

which we have more reason <strong>to</strong> accept. An in principle objection goes further.<br />

It argues that no account of divine action could have any explana<strong>to</strong>ry<br />

force. Even if such an account were true, there is no conceivable state of<br />

affairs which it could be said <strong>to</strong> explain.<br />

In this chapter, I shall argue that this in principle objection is wrong.<br />

One can at least conceive of situations in which talk of divine action would<br />

be explana<strong>to</strong>ry. In this sense, the atheist has no “silver bullet,” which will<br />

“put a merciful end <strong>to</strong> all the nonsense.” 1 He cannot assume, without further<br />

investigation, that a proposed theistic explanation is worthless. But<br />

he can ask if this particular s<strong>to</strong>ry of divine action constitutes a potential<br />

explanation of this particular state of affairs. And the key question here is<br />

that posed by David Hume: Is this state of affairs what we would expect of<br />

“a very powerful, wise, <strong>and</strong> benevolent Deity?” 2 If it is not, then no talk of<br />

divine action could explain it.<br />

But I’m leaping ahead. Let me pause for a moment <strong>to</strong> summarise the<br />

conclusions I have reached. What is required of an account of divine action<br />

if it is <strong>to</strong> be considered a potential explanation of some state of affairs? In<br />

Chapter 3, I described the fi rst condition that such a proposed explanation<br />

must meet. It must do more than posit the mere existence of a crea<strong>to</strong>r God<br />

(3.2.3). Such a posit fails <strong>to</strong> single out the fact <strong>to</strong> be explained, since on the<br />

theistic hypothesis whatever occurred would happen because God willed it.<br />

If a proposed theistic explanation is <strong>to</strong> have any signifi cant degree of empirical<br />

content, it must view the explan<strong>and</strong>um as a means <strong>to</strong>wards a divinelywilled<br />

end. It must posit the existence of a particular divine intention. A<br />

second condition has <strong>to</strong> do with the coherence of theism (3.3). We need <strong>to</strong><br />

have some confi dence that the theistic hypothesis does not embody hidden

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!