15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

184 Notes<br />

50. Swinburne, Existence of God, 53.<br />

51. Ibid., 65.<br />

52. Ibid., 64.<br />

53. Ibid., 60. Note that Swinburne’s defi nition of background knowledge effectively<br />

restricts it <strong>to</strong> observational evidence. By excluding our best theories,<br />

Swinburne signifi cantly (<strong>and</strong> conveniently) narrows its scope.<br />

54. Swinburne, Existence of God, 146.<br />

55. Ibid., 65–66.<br />

56. Ibid., 16.<br />

57. Ibid., 17.<br />

58. Sobel, “Probabilities, Subjective <strong>and</strong> Objective,” 9.<br />

59. Swinburne, Existence of God, 71.<br />

60. Ibid.<br />

61. Ibid., 112–31.<br />

62. Musgrave, “Kuhn’s Second Thoughts,” 292.<br />

63. Ibid., 290.<br />

64. Bartholomew, “Lyell <strong>and</strong> Evolution,” 294.<br />

65. Ibid., 294–95.<br />

66. Draper, “God, Science, <strong>and</strong> Naturalism,” 295–96.<br />

67. Carrier, “Argument from Biogenesis,” 742.<br />

68. Prevost, “Swinburne, Mackie <strong>and</strong> Bayes’s Theorem,” 181.<br />

69. Swinburne, Existence of God, 53.<br />

70. Mackie, Miracle of <strong>Theism</strong>, 100.<br />

71. Swinburne, Existence of God, 97.<br />

72. Swinburne, The Christian God, 160.<br />

73. Hume, “Dialogues,” iv (61); Plantinga, Does God Have a Nature?, 47.<br />

74. Banner, Justifi cation of Science, 152–53.<br />

75. Popper, Logic of Scientifi c Discovery, §43 (126–28).<br />

76. Thagard, “The Best <strong>Explanation</strong>,” 186.<br />

77. Ibid., 184. As Thagard notes, auxiliary hypotheses, introduced in an ad hoc<br />

manner, do not detract from simplicity if they are themselves corroborated,<br />

if they help <strong>to</strong> explain new facts, or are “shared by competing theories.”<br />

78. Popper, Logic of Scientifi c Discovery, §46 (131).<br />

79. Van Inwagen, “Problem of Evil,” 162 n. 6.<br />

80. Draper, “Pain <strong>and</strong> Pleasure,” 332.<br />

81. Van Inwagen, “Problem of Evil,” 151.<br />

82. Ibid., 139–40; Plantinga, God, Freedom <strong>and</strong> Evil, 28.<br />

83. Van Inwagen, “Problem of Evil,” 140–43. Van Inwagen speaks of an his<strong>to</strong>rian<br />

defending the character of Richard III, but I have transposed it in<strong>to</strong> that<br />

of a lawyer defending a client, <strong>to</strong> make his point clearer.<br />

84. I have already suggested (5.4.3.2) that such scepticism undermines the theist’s<br />

explana<strong>to</strong>ry claims as much as the atheist’s argument from evil. But<br />

that’s not the point I’m making here.<br />

85. Van Inwagen, “Problem of Evil,”136. In fact, van Inwagen offers two parallel<br />

arguments, but I shall examine just the fi rst, since the issues raised by<br />

the second are no different.<br />

86. Van Inwagen, “Problem of Evil,”153.<br />

87. Ibid., 155.<br />

88. Ibid., 139.<br />

89. Would it suffi ce <strong>to</strong> show that the auxiliary hypothesis is likely, given the<br />

central hypothesis? Would it be enough <strong>to</strong> show that if theism were true, the<br />

proposed scenario is plausible (ibid., 139). Well, it would help. But the a<strong>to</strong>mist’s<br />

spike hypothesis doesn’t seem <strong>to</strong> have even this much in its favour.<br />

90. Ibid., 153.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!