15.05.2013 Views

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

Theism and Explanation - Appeared-to-Blogly

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

74 <strong>Theism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Explanation</strong><br />

(1) There exists a rational agent A with intended goal G.<br />

(2) A has beliefs B 1 , B 2 , . . . B n relating <strong>to</strong> the attainment of G.<br />

(3) If B 1 , B 2 , . . . B n were true, E would be the best way of achieving G.<br />

(4) Rational agents always choose the best way of achieving their goals.<br />

(5) Therefore A will do E.<br />

The key premises <strong>to</strong> note are (3) <strong>and</strong> (4). The objection levelled by Smith<br />

<strong>and</strong> Pennock assumes that our explanation is nomological, that it cites laws<br />

connecting the agent’s observed behaviour with some a particular set of<br />

beliefs <strong>and</strong> desires. But whether or not such laws exist (Appendix 3.3.1), an<br />

explanation of this form does not rely on them. What it relies on is a rationality<br />

principle (5.2 <strong>and</strong> Appendix 1.3). It predicts an agent’s behaviour by<br />

assuming that she will act in a way that is consistent with her beliefs <strong>and</strong><br />

desires in order <strong>to</strong> achieve her goal (5.2–5.3).<br />

In other words, the objection put forward by both Smith <strong>and</strong> Pennock<br />

assumes a false dicho<strong>to</strong>my. It assumes that the world is either governed by<br />

natural laws or it is the product of a mere “whim” on the part of a supernatural<br />

agent. But these are not the only options. The world could, conceivably,<br />

be the work of a supernatural agent acting rationally in order <strong>to</strong><br />

achieve his goals. If we posit a particular goal, we might be able <strong>to</strong> predict<br />

his behaviour. The fact that this agent is capable of working miracles is neither<br />

here nor there. The key question is: What would be the most rational<br />

way for such an agent <strong>to</strong> act in order <strong>to</strong> achieve this goal? The answer may<br />

or may not include miracles. 53<br />

4.4.4 Hume’s Argument<br />

What if we did decide that the most rational way for God <strong>to</strong> act, in these<br />

circumstances, was by way of a miracle? Then a miracle is what we would<br />

expect <strong>to</strong> observe, given the theistic hypothesis. But the atheist might simply<br />

refuse <strong>to</strong> recognise any alleged miracle as a miracle. He might, in support<br />

of this refusal, appeal <strong>to</strong> David Hume’s argument, that it is always<br />

more probable that a miracle report should be false than that a miracle has<br />

occurred. If Hume is right, then we would never be in a position <strong>to</strong> verify<br />

this particular theistic prediction. We would never be justifi ed in regarding<br />

any observed fact as a miracle. 54 If this is correct, then at least one group<br />

of proposed theistic explanations—those which posit miracles—seems<br />

doomed <strong>to</strong> failure.<br />

But was Hume right? Hume’s apparently simple argument, which he<br />

hoped would settle the question once <strong>and</strong> for all, 55 is still being debated.<br />

I cannot hope <strong>to</strong> end the debate here. Let me just point out a weakness in<br />

Hume’s argument, which highlights the need for a fuller discussion. The<br />

argument rests on the idea that we can estimate the prior probability of a<br />

miracle occurring, <strong>and</strong> that this prior probability is exceedingly low. But

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!