12.12.2012 Views

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

106 The Praeger H<strong>and</strong>book of Education <strong>and</strong> Psychology<br />

This is an idealized situation, a normative goal that educators can strive to achieve in their<br />

classrooms. In the classroom, the teacher has a “more than equal” role <strong>and</strong> the authority of greater<br />

knowledge about the subject. In which case it is doubly important for the teacher to beware of<br />

becoming a “dominating participant.” Due to structural inequities in society, people will be able to<br />

engage in “critical rational discourse” at different levels <strong>and</strong> in different contexts. By striving for<br />

the ideal speech situation; the settlement of disagreements through communicative rationality;<br />

<strong>and</strong> a pedagogical practice informed by the goals, Habermas implicates all of society in a<br />

normative call to come up with solutions to structural inequity. This in turn reaffirms Habermas’s<br />

fundamental belief in the democratic process. Indeed, Pusey (1987) characterizes Habermas’s<br />

concept of democracy “as a process of shared learning” (p. 120).<br />

What, then, is the role of a university, specifically, in a democracy? In Toward a Rational<br />

Society (1970) Habermas details the relationship of the university to democracy. The role of the<br />

university consists of four concurrent tasks that resonate with Habermas’s earlier conception of<br />

knowledge interests. First, research at a university pursues the technical mastery of nature <strong>and</strong> the<br />

production of new generations of scientists. Second, the university is a place where students learn<br />

practical knowledge, cultural knowledge, which prepares them for life in modern society as well<br />

as provide the “extracurricular” but necessary knowledge for a profession (like quick decision<br />

making skills for a future doctor). Third is to produce, interpret, <strong>and</strong> pass on the “cultural tradition<br />

of society.” And, finally, the university is a place of development of political consciousness<br />

(pp. 1–3).<br />

Habermas claims that, in Germany during the 1960s, the university system faces a crisis. In<br />

his eyes, the university was pulled in different directions by the technical knowledge interest <strong>and</strong><br />

emancipatory knowledge interests. On the one h<strong>and</strong> the university was increasingly stressing the<br />

importance of developing technical knowledge for industrial applications. On the other h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

the university was increasingly oriented to the politicization of students in the post-War era.<br />

However, the university, as an institution, remained unchanged in organization since the Middle<br />

Ages. Habermas presents this qu<strong>and</strong>ary as having two different solutions. The university could<br />

either retreat into depoliticized, factory-like knowledge production or else the university could<br />

“assert itself within the democratic tradition” (p. 6). Either way, the university has to change its<br />

structure. Habermas’s belief in the democratic tradition leads him to “substantiate [his] vote for<br />

this second possibility by trying to demonstrate the affinity <strong>and</strong> inner relation of the enterprise of<br />

knowledge on the university level to the democratic form of decision-making” (p. 6).<br />

Habermas reinforces what he considers democracy. It isn’t the formal political apparatus of<br />

modern welfare states, instead he argues for political decision making that is in a “Kantian<br />

manner.” This means that “only reason should have force” <strong>and</strong> that consensus is arrived in a<br />

discussion free of coercion (p. 7). Kantian <strong>and</strong> Habermasian reason is not purpose-driven; it is<br />

based on reflection in the tradition of Enlightenment philosophy. In the context of the university,<br />

across all disciplines, Habermas call for a “philosophical enlightenment” that “illustrate[s] a selfreflection<br />

of the sciences in which the latter become critically aware of their own presuppositions”<br />

(p. 8). This self-reflection within research traditions <strong>and</strong> the pedagogical process will yield<br />

more critical <strong>and</strong> complex ways of underst<strong>and</strong>ing the relation between different subjects <strong>and</strong><br />

courses of inquiry. This also brings new “continuity” to the university campus: “critical argument<br />

serves in the end only to disclose the commingling of basic methodological assumptions <strong>and</strong><br />

action-orienting self-underst<strong>and</strong>ing. If this is so, then no matter how much the self-reflection<br />

of the sciences <strong>and</strong> the rational discussion of political decisions differ <strong>and</strong> must be carefully<br />

distinguished, they are still connected by the common form or critical inquiry” (p. 10). Further,<br />

Habermas argues that only through this reflection process can the university system achieve the<br />

three goals that transcend the technical or instrumental goal of advancing the science of industry.<br />

A university in a democracy, then, becomes a site for the rigorous advancement of critical

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!