12.12.2012 Views

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Herbert Marcuse 165<br />

An Essay on Liberation (1969) <strong>and</strong> Counterrevolution <strong>and</strong> Revolt (1972)—helping to articulate<br />

a politics for the New Left emphasizing the power of the outcast <strong>and</strong> disenfranchised in general.<br />

His case is not for the working party per se to gain power, but that the decisive factor is the<br />

discontent, the great refusal of the nonintegrated individual. The radical intellectual is again key<br />

to the opening of the social imagination, just as the radical act is requisite for the liberation of the<br />

individual, the opening to true needs.<br />

This concern with needs was to characterize Marcuse’s later philosophy, particularly in An<br />

Essay on Liberation. In Marcuse’s view, happiness is not ancillary, but central, to freedom.<br />

Freedom, in turn, necessarily involves the meeting of our true needs. Without such freedom, real<br />

happiness is impossible for human beings. Still, it is necessary to note, particularly for those<br />

who would like to see, <strong>and</strong> have seen, Marcuse as an apologist for “free” sexuality <strong>and</strong> the<br />

“me” generation, that Marcuse is arguing against a purely subjective <strong>and</strong> selfish happiness in<br />

his argument for the meeting of human needs. He argues that happiness is inherently connected<br />

to the transformation of social conditions <strong>and</strong> individual consciousness, that there is a clear<br />

distinction between “higher” <strong>and</strong> “lower” pleasures obscured (<strong>and</strong> inverted to a great extent) by<br />

contemporary culture: more <strong>and</strong> more, we recognize ourselves in our commodities; we define<br />

ourselves by what we own, what we have, <strong>and</strong> what we need to get. True needs are essential to<br />

human survival <strong>and</strong> development; false needs are superimposed on us <strong>and</strong> serve the interests of<br />

repressive social forces. Technology, in Marcuse’s philosophy, plays a crucial role here: rather<br />

than being directed toward the maximization of profit (in all its forms), technology could (<strong>and</strong><br />

perhaps ought) to be directed toward the satisfaction of true needs.<br />

Like very few others thinkers, Marcuse was willing to embrace a notion of social transformation<br />

that includes the sensual, sensuous, <strong>and</strong> receptive as the foundation for our society, morality,<br />

rationality. It is again necessary to note as a response to vocal (though ultimately misinformed)<br />

critics that Marcuse’s vision involves not the unbridled genital expression of our libido, but a<br />

nonrepressive sublimation of the sex instincts, the “eroticization of the entire personality,” the<br />

freedom to truly play. Sexuality is, Marcuse argues (again similar to Wilhelm Reich in this),<br />

transformative <strong>and</strong> vital. Its free expression leads not to a progression of lewd, lascivious acts, but<br />

rather their minimization. Opening taboo to the light would incorporate these impulses (now only<br />

allowed “neurotic” expression in general society) into constructive society; it would transform<br />

so-called perversion into creativity. Marcuse did not advocate orgasmic expression (like Reich) as<br />

the key to liberation <strong>and</strong> social transformation, but rather the liberated Eros that would ultimately<br />

express across the levels of our human existence. In a rational world, sexuality, in Marcuse’s terms,<br />

would cease to be a threat to culture <strong>and</strong> instead lead to culture-building; the human organism<br />

ought to exist not as an instrument of alienated labor, but as the subject of self-realization <strong>and</strong><br />

social transformation together in the meeting of true needs.<br />

What opens the space for this new imagination was a major focus in Marcuse’s last book, The<br />

Aesthetic Dimension: A Critique of Marxist Aesthetics (1978). In a turn back to the beginnings of<br />

his writing <strong>and</strong> work (his 1922 dissertation on the German artist-novel), he argues for authentic art<br />

(as literature, primarily) as the authentic radical act. Similarly to the way he treats fantasy in Eros<br />

<strong>and</strong> Civilization, Marcuse argues for authentic art as integral to the Marxist social revolution; art<br />

(<strong>and</strong> again, literature especially) provides <strong>and</strong> catalyzes the imagination <strong>and</strong> consciousness for true<br />

revolution. True, authentic art breaks through mystification, through solidified reality. In effect,<br />

authentic art moves us in our hermeneutic experience beyond, opening spaces in the imagination<br />

for emancipation. This theme of emancipation, liberation, or revolution, of demystification, is<br />

part of the inner logic of authentic art, rather than its explicit style or content.<br />

Marcuse’s exploration in Aesthetic Dimension emphasizes his lifelong argument: the decisive<br />

fact of progression <strong>and</strong> evolution, over <strong>and</strong> against repression <strong>and</strong> fascism, is the liberated subjectivity<br />

of individuals, present to true needs, intelligence <strong>and</strong> passion, imagination <strong>and</strong> conscience.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!