12.12.2012 Views

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Where Is the Mind Supposed to Be? 605<br />

this issue first, it is true that language is in the world <strong>and</strong> does, in a sense, “operate” on that world<br />

in a tool-like manner; this is not unlike how a shovel operates on the soil it moves. What language<br />

cannot do is mesh or join with that world. To do that, two things are required: ideas must originate<br />

in the senses, <strong>and</strong> the world has to be an equal partner in the enterprise. Nominalists limit the<br />

world’s role to offering up particular objects. The mind is the star in this scenario; it is the mind<br />

that acts on particulars in the process known as “induction” to create the generality or regularity<br />

that is associated with underst<strong>and</strong>ing.<br />

Duns Scotus, writing some twenty years before Ockham, may have been the first to put mind<br />

<strong>and</strong> world on equal footing. Regularity or universality, like rationality in humans or, in later<br />

centuries, gravity or photosynthesis, is present in nature. Furthermore, the role it plays in making<br />

itself known is as active as that of the human mind. Scotus was the first to posit a relationship of<br />

true reciprocity between mind <strong>and</strong> world. This last point requires some elaboration. The middle<br />

ages were dominated by religion; both Scotus <strong>and</strong> Ockham, in fact, were members of a religious<br />

order as well as academicians. The vexing philosophical issues that Scotus struggled with was<br />

how to respond to Aristotle, whose newly discovered writings, lost to the West for a thous<strong>and</strong><br />

years, were wreaking havoc with the Catholic church. Scotus, <strong>and</strong> before him, Aquinas, tried to<br />

square Aristotle’s notion of natural law with divine power, evidenced by God’s spontaneous will.<br />

Contrary to Aristotle’s teachings, the scholastics thought that God could, if he so willed, change<br />

a human embryo into a tree. Contingency rather than necessity was the order of the day. Scotus’s<br />

solution to this vexing problem was to view indeterminacy in positive rather than negative terms.<br />

Contingency does not represent nature falling short in some way. Rather, it represents the wideranging<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> creativity of God’s thought. At the moment of creation, God sees all the<br />

possibilities open to him, now <strong>and</strong> in the future. In a sense, the alternatives are all spelled out<br />

ahead of time. It is the function of God’s will, when the proper time comes, to determine which,<br />

if any, of the possibilities he actualizes.<br />

Scotus’s decision to put possibility on the same continuum with necessity humbled intellect<br />

at the same time that it elevated will. It is will, at both the divine <strong>and</strong> the human level, that<br />

converts imperfectly understood possibilities into fully realized facts. Confused knowledge,<br />

grasped qualitatively (e.g., metaphorically), is the first step in the acquisition of more certain<br />

knowledge. The brilliance of Scotus’s solution was to allow for a type of knowing that could put<br />

the mind in direct relationship to the object or event the inquirer is attempting to know. Individual<br />

objects are an amalgam of particular <strong>and</strong> general attributes. The mind discovers generality; it does<br />

not, as Ockham would argue, create it. The discovery process is a joint one. Both “object <strong>and</strong><br />

author,” to use Scotus’s language, play active roles. It surfaces as mere possibility <strong>and</strong> is grasped<br />

by the mind as a sign (e.g., called a “phantasm” by Scotus). Charles S<strong>and</strong>ers Peirce, who built on<br />

Scotus’s ideas in the nineteenth century, would liken this imaginative rendering of generality to<br />

that of a metaphor; a modern-day example might be seeing the plant as a “food factory.” When the<br />

object is viewed through the lens of the sign, it contributes to the discovery process by allowing<br />

certain features to emerge in sharp relief while blocking other, presumably irrelevant features.<br />

The term Scotus used to describe this hybrid sign-object was, appropriately, that of the “physical<br />

universal.” Drawing on our modern-day example, this means that during the qualitative first stage<br />

of coming to underst<strong>and</strong>, the individual can truly see the plant as a factory that produces food—<br />

see that there is a production process going on within the confines of the leaf, that these products<br />

are warehoused, that a waste product is given off, <strong>and</strong> so forth. Two points are worth noting here:<br />

Scotus’s scholastic realism allowed for the mind to mesh or interrelate with the world in the early<br />

stages of underst<strong>and</strong>ing; concepts are immediately obtained from objects. (This underst<strong>and</strong>ing, of<br />

course, must be reformulated as a proposition.) Second, Scotus’s view of God (<strong>and</strong> nature) is an<br />

intellectually friendly one. By building essence into being, God all but ensures that our experience<br />

with nature will be a conceptual as well as a sensory one. Furthermore, although God does not

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!