12.12.2012 Views

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Where Is the Mind Supposed to Be? 609<br />

Rene Descartes in his famous “structures of thought” argument. Similarly, information processors<br />

seek to track the flow of data from input, through abstraction, to propositional knowledge.<br />

A machine unimaginable in Locke’s time, the high-speed computer, has been appropriated for<br />

this task. The argument goes like this: When a computer program, designed to mimic processes<br />

used by humans, produces behavior that parallels that observed in a real-life situation, the result<br />

is said to constitute a “sufficiency proof,” which validates the information processing model.<br />

The other two learning theories talked about earlier—the sociocultural <strong>and</strong> social constructivist<br />

approaches—might appear to have an advantage over the head encased views just described when<br />

it comes to knowledge validation because the processes they emphasize are overt rather than<br />

covert. This is possible, I submit, because socioculturalists <strong>and</strong> social constructivists have made<br />

a virtue out of what Scotus <strong>and</strong> Peirce would consider a great weakness in current approaches to<br />

learning: This is the distinction, nominalist in origin, between content <strong>and</strong> process. As has been<br />

shown, this distinction is a key feature of rationalism, empiricism, <strong>and</strong> even of Kant’s valiant<br />

attempt to meld the two (see below). Thus, sociocultural theorists argue that mental activity, like<br />

the physical activity involved in tailoring or weaving, can be externalized <strong>and</strong> modeled because<br />

it is content free. The comprehension-monitoring activity taught during reciprocal teaching,<br />

activities such as summarizing <strong>and</strong> question asking, while intended for reading, can be applied to<br />

oral-language situations as well. Social constructivists make a similar point about “language-ing.”<br />

They reject what they consider to be the outdated, modernist view of language as a container or<br />

holder of knowledge <strong>and</strong> meaning. The function of language is to manage or coordinate human<br />

relationships. Both sets of theorists, then, build on the notion that there is process without content.<br />

History, including intellectual history, is filled with “what ifs.” One of the major what ifs<br />

relates to Peirce’s effort in the late nineteenth century to resurrect Scotus’s unique version of<br />

what, from the present-day perspective, could only be called “realist constructivism.” Peirce<br />

argued forcefully that Scotus’s view did not get a fair hearing in the fourteenth century. It lost out<br />

to Ockham’s nominalism on political <strong>and</strong> not philosophical grounds. Scotus’s belief that generals<br />

or universals actually exist in individuals was viewed with suspicion by the humanists, who joined<br />

forces with the nominalists to defeat this notion. They equated this idea with a more conservative<br />

stance toward authority, the subtext for them apparently being that it takes extraordinary expertise<br />

to tease out the regularity posited by Scotus. In that sense, the aversion nominalists <strong>and</strong> humanists<br />

felt toward Scotus’s realism is not unlike the aversion social constructivists feel toward scientific<br />

realists—a major factor in the ongoing “science wars.”<br />

Peirce did not just base his realist constructivism on Scotus’s five centuries old work. He had a<br />

more recent model, Immanuel Kant, who Peirce termed “his revered master.” Kant is best known<br />

for his attempt in the late eighteenth century to reconcile the dramatically different stances taken<br />

by rationalists <strong>and</strong> empiricists. In the first approach, reason runs roughshod over the senses, while<br />

in the second the converse often appears to be the case. Kant’s well-known solution to these<br />

problems was twofold: he argued that our perceptual apparatus is structured in such a way as to<br />

compel us to compound or synthesize sensory input to produce “bundles” of spatially located<br />

<strong>and</strong> temporally ordered sensation. Similarly, our cognitive apparatus all but m<strong>and</strong>ates that we<br />

conceptualize experience in certain predetermined ways. Thus, we always attend to the number<br />

of objects in the experience, the intensity or “realness” of the experience, the scope of time of the<br />

experience—whether, for example, we are dealing with things that are happening now or that will<br />

happen in the future. Finally, we take note, again in a general sense, of the nature of the relation<br />

we are coming to terms with—whether, for example, it is an object–attribute or cause–effect<br />

relationship.<br />

Less well known but of equal importance to Peirce was Kant’s insistence that what we come to<br />

know about objects is their form or essence. Kant was the first modern philosopher to resurrect<br />

the notion that both commonness (i.e., universals) <strong>and</strong> particularity coexist in individual things.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!