12.12.2012 Views

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

128 The Praeger H<strong>and</strong>book of Education <strong>and</strong> Psychology<br />

begins with the universal <strong>and</strong> then moves to the parts of the whole, <strong>and</strong> empiricism, which he<br />

says starts in an explanation of the parts. He continues,<br />

To be radical, an empiricism must neither admit into its constructions any element that is not directly<br />

experienced, nor exclude from them any element that is directly experienced. For such a philosophy, the<br />

relations that connect experiences must themselves be experienced relations, <strong>and</strong> any kind of relation<br />

experienced must be accounted as “real” as any thing else in the system. [James’s emphasis] (p. 533)<br />

James’s major explanation of his theory was published in Essays in Radical Empiricism (1912). In<br />

the editor’s preface of this posthumous collection, Ralph Barton Perry says James valued radical<br />

empiricism more than pragmatism (pp. xvi–xvii). Perry adds that the term itself first appeared<br />

in print in The Will to Believe (1896/1967), <strong>and</strong> James defined it as a philosophic attitude<br />

(p. xix). James goes even further in The Meaning of Truth (1911), specifying that “Radical<br />

empiricism consists (1) first of a postulate, (2) next of a statement of fact, (3) <strong>and</strong> finally of a<br />

generalized conclusion” (p. xvi). Radical empiricism may also be defined as pure experience, or<br />

the inseparability of the knower <strong>and</strong> the known. He ends Essays in Radical Empiricism saying,<br />

“all philosophies are hypotheses, to which all our faculties, emotional as well as logical, help<br />

us ...” (p. 279).<br />

JAMES THE POSTFORMALIST<br />

William James foreshadows twenty-first-century postformalism in three ways: in his conceptualization<br />

of truth, in his acknowledgement of complexity, <strong>and</strong> in his phenomenological, or as<br />

it may more properly be called, his proto-phenomenological writing, which in interpretations by<br />

theorists such as Husserl has been reduced to a positivist version bearing only partial similarity<br />

to the original. James alludes to the uneasy reception given to pragmatism when he writes in The<br />

Meaning of Truth (1911) about “warfare” (p. xv) between the pragmatists <strong>and</strong> the nonpragmatists.<br />

But he is firm in his notion that truth is ever-changing, saying,<br />

“Truth” is thus in process of formation like all other things. It consists not in conformity or correspondence<br />

with an externally fixed archetype or model. Such a thing would be irrelevant even if we knew it to exist.<br />

(p. xv)<br />

He is even less prosaic in The Will to Believe (1896/1967) when he writes, “Objective evidence <strong>and</strong><br />

certitude are doubtless very fine ideals to play with, but where on this moonlit <strong>and</strong> dream-visited<br />

planet are they found?” (p. 725). James recognizes human beings for their complexity, writing<br />

in Talks to Teachers (1899/1958), “Man is too complex a being for light to be thrown on his real<br />

efficiency by measuring any one mental faculty taken apart from its consensus in the working<br />

whole” (p. 96). He continues by arguing that any attempt to quantify human underst<strong>and</strong>ing is<br />

reductive <strong>and</strong> suspect, saying, “There are as many types of apperception as there are possible<br />

ways in which an incoming experience may be reacted on by an individual mind” (p. 112).<br />

James is describing a truly human science. His intellectual descendent, Husserl, in contrast, takes<br />

the notion of lived world <strong>and</strong> attempts to make of it a phenomenology that is positivistic in its<br />

conceptualization. Philosopher G.B. Madison, in The Hermeneutics of Postmodernity (1988),<br />

describes Husserl’s obsession with the idea of a unified science, <strong>and</strong> his construction of science<br />

as a hierarchy with phenomenology at the top (p. 43). Ironically, James’s conceptualization is<br />

closer to the postformal model than is Husserl’s, although James does not invoke issues of power<br />

<strong>and</strong> social justice. As Madison puts it in reference to James, “Pioneers, like Moses, do not always<br />

make it to the Promised L<strong>and</strong>” (p. 192, n27).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!