12.12.2012 Views

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

Educational Psychology—Limitations and Possibilities

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Introduction 17<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ings do not simply dictate our pedagogical strategies—instead, they inform them. One<br />

can still use a wide variety of teaching methodologies in light of such knowledge. Teachers by<br />

no means are condemned to teach the same way.<br />

If we underst<strong>and</strong> that learning takes place in context <strong>and</strong> in process, then we begin to appreciate<br />

the impact of the prior knowledge students bring to a classroom on the learning process. Many<br />

boys coming from working-class backgrounds, for example, may carry with them to school an<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of academic work as an effeminate pursuit. Such prior knowledge plays a dramatic<br />

role in shaping their disposition toward learning. An educational psychologist or a teacher who<br />

does not know this operates at a severe disadvantage. S<strong>and</strong>ra Racionero <strong>and</strong> Rosa Valls in their<br />

chapter on dialogic learning are well aware of such dynamics <strong>and</strong> maintain that teachers who<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> them focus more attention on the nature <strong>and</strong> needs of the learner. This moves pedagogy<br />

away from the mechanistic focus on the teacher as the “unique agent in the teaching–learning<br />

process.” Again, such insight does not dictate pedagogical method. To focus on the nature <strong>and</strong><br />

needs of the learner does not mean that teachers do not ever confront students with bodies of<br />

knowledge. There is still much analysis to do on just what it means to be more attentive to the<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> needs of the learner.<br />

To be attentive to the nature <strong>and</strong> needs of the learner in a critical interpretivist sense does not<br />

mean that we focus our attention on natural <strong>and</strong> ready-made students. It also does not mean that<br />

we attend to the learner so we can “normalize” him or her—fit him or her to the needs of dominant<br />

institutions. Here is where critical interpretivists have to be very careful. We can develop the most<br />

child-centered pedagogies possible that not only focus our attention on the nature <strong>and</strong> needs of<br />

the learner but allow the learner to produce his or her own knowledge about the world. If such<br />

knowledge is not problematized, subjected to ideological, discursive, <strong>and</strong> cultural analysis, then<br />

we may empower students to become hegemonized by the needs of the dominant culture. While<br />

critical interpretivists most definitely want students who actively participate in the world, we also<br />

want students with the ability to ask hard questions of the knowledges they encounter <strong>and</strong> even<br />

the knowledges they produce. Such a goal requires even more of the teacher who must underst<strong>and</strong><br />

the nature <strong>and</strong> needs of the student in a larger sociocultural <strong>and</strong> political context. Such a teacher<br />

must always be aware of the political consequences of particular epistemologies, psychologies,<br />

<strong>and</strong> pedagogies.<br />

MECHANISM AND THE CENTRAL PROCESSING MECHANISM<br />

With these epistemological underst<strong>and</strong>ings in mind one is better equipped to underst<strong>and</strong> how<br />

mechanistic educational psychology has come to “believe in” a central processing mechanism<br />

(CPM). Indeed, the primary task of such a paradigm is to delineate the nature of this hidden<br />

mechanism <strong>and</strong> how it operates. To study it mechanists must remove it from everything else <strong>and</strong><br />

then in its isolation delineate exactly how it represents the real world, categorizes the different<br />

aspects of the world, draws on stored memories, learns, etc. This mechanism st<strong>and</strong>s apart from<br />

everything on which it operates <strong>and</strong> must be described in this way—the focus is on its universal<br />

properties. The capacity or efficiency of this CPM is what mechanists claim to be measuring<br />

when they administer psychological tests. Of course, the problem is that since we don’t have<br />

any clear underst<strong>and</strong>ing of what the CPM is <strong>and</strong> little underst<strong>and</strong>ing of what exactly constitutes<br />

its high-level <strong>and</strong> efficient operation, then we’re not exactly sure what such tests are measuring.<br />

When we bring our epistemological insights to bear in this situation, we can uncover further<br />

confusion about the relation of the CPM to social, cultural, political, economic, <strong>and</strong> philosophical<br />

context.<br />

Mark Garrison in his chapter on psychometrics extends these observations, maintaining that<br />

there is an irrational dimension to the measurement work of mechanistic psychology. Garrison

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!