06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

124 <strong>Wellbeing</strong>, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Social</strong> <strong>Justice</strong><br />

‘reset’ our cultural <strong>and</strong> social norms, which would lead to less pressure,<br />

stress <strong>and</strong> fewer anxieties? Some alternative views of living, such as<br />

those advanced by deep ecology thinkers (e.g. Naess 1973, 1984), are<br />

based on the view that with a different set of desires, <strong>and</strong> a different<br />

appreciation of certain experiences <strong>and</strong> values, we would be able to<br />

live not only in an ecologically sustainable way, but also have higher<br />

levels of wellbeing. In sum, the desire-fulfilment theory is interesting<br />

<strong>and</strong> arguably plausible at the individual level, <strong>and</strong> also at the general<br />

level as a theoretical approach to wellbeing, which can make ample use<br />

of counterfactual <strong>and</strong> hypothetical thinking <strong>and</strong> conditions. But it is<br />

much trickier to think about wellbeing from a macro or third-person<br />

perspective in the world as it is, in which we don’t have information on<br />

how each person’s preferences have been formed <strong>and</strong> influenced.<br />

How does the objective list theory fare? Objective list theories<br />

are accounts of wellbeing that list items that make our lives better,<br />

independent of our own view on this. <strong>The</strong> claim of objective list theories<br />

is that there is an irreducible plurality of issues that make up wellbeing;<br />

wellbeing is plural <strong>and</strong> cannot be reduced to a single thing. Secondly,<br />

those items are objectively good for us, whether or not we attach any value<br />

to (or desire) those items. Hence items such as being healthy, or having<br />

friends, or feeling well, are all good for us, whether we personally value<br />

them or not.<br />

What are some of the main strengths <strong>and</strong> weaknesses of the objective<br />

list theories? Objective list theories are generally criticised for not<br />

respecting people’s views about their own lives, <strong>and</strong> hence taking away<br />

the authority to decide the quality of those lives from the agents leading<br />

them: in other words, for being paternalistic. Who is to decide that,<br />

say, social relationships are good for us? Now, this seems a very valid<br />

critique if we use an objective list theory for purely descriptive <strong>and</strong> firstperson<br />

truth-seeking purposes, as the vast literature in philosophy does.<br />

But if one uses accounts of wellbeing for policy or political purposes,<br />

the public nature of the dimensions of wellbeing is rather important.<br />

This relates to what political philosophers have called ‘the publicity<br />

criterion’: if wellbeing is used for purposes of institutional design or<br />

policy making, those principles used need to be capable of being known<br />

by all to be satisfied in society (Rawls 2009; Anderson 2010, 85).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!