06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

52 <strong>Wellbeing</strong>, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Social</strong> <strong>Justice</strong><br />

among scholars of the capability approach; for example, Sabina Alkire<br />

(2005, 122) described the capability approach as the proposition “that<br />

social arrangements should be evaluated according to the extent of<br />

freedom people have to promote or achieve functionings they value”.<br />

However, if we fully take into account that functionings can be positive<br />

but also negative (see 2.6.2), we should also acknowledge that our lives<br />

are better if they contain fewer of the functionings that are negative,<br />

such as physical violence or stress. Alkire’s proposition should therefore<br />

minimally be extended by adding “<strong>and</strong> to promote the weakening of<br />

those functionings that have a negative value”. 29<br />

However, what is relevant is not only which opportunities are<br />

open to us individually, hence in a piecemeal way, but rather which<br />

combinations or sets of potential functionings are open to us. For example,<br />

suppose you are a low-skilled poor single parent who lives in a society<br />

without decent social provisions. Take the following functionings: (1)<br />

to hold a job, which will require you to spend many hours on working<br />

<strong>and</strong> commuting, but will generate the income needed to properly feed<br />

yourself <strong>and</strong> your family; (2) to care for your children at home <strong>and</strong> give<br />

them all the attention, care <strong>and</strong> supervision they need. In a piecemeal<br />

analysis, both (1) <strong>and</strong> (2) are opportunities open to that parent, but<br />

they are not both together open to her. <strong>The</strong> point about the capability<br />

approach is precisely that it is comprehensive; we must ask which sets<br />

of capabilities are open to us, that is: can you simultaneously provide<br />

for your family <strong>and</strong> properly care for <strong>and</strong> supervise your children? Or<br />

are you rather forced to make some hard, perhaps even tragic choices<br />

between two functionings which are both central <strong>and</strong> valuable?<br />

Note that while most types of capability analysis require<br />

interpersonal comparisons, one could also use the capability approach<br />

to evaluate the wellbeing or wellbeing freedom of one person at one<br />

point in time (e.g. evaluate her situation against a capability yardstick)<br />

or to evaluate the changes in her wellbeing or wellbeing freedom over<br />

29 Moreover, further extensions of this proposition may be needed. One issue is that<br />

we should not only focus on capabilities that people value, but also on capabilities<br />

that they do not, but should, value (see section 2.7.2). Another issue is that the<br />

evaluative space should not necessarily be restricted to capabilities only, but could<br />

also be functionings, or a combination of functionings <strong>and</strong> capabilities (see section<br />

2.6.5).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!