06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

182 <strong>Wellbeing</strong>, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Social</strong> <strong>Justice</strong><br />

better reached by a coordinated commitment to individual action or by<br />

relying on market mechanisms. Adherents of public choice theory would<br />

stress that giving the government the power to deliver those goods<br />

will have many unintended but foreseeable negative consequences,<br />

which are much more important than the positive contributions the<br />

government could make. 3<br />

A second reason why capabilitarian political theories may not<br />

see the government as the only, or primary, agent of justice, relates<br />

to the distinction between ideal theories of justice (which describe<br />

those normative principles that would be met in a just world, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

institutions that would meet those principles) versus non-ideal theory<br />

(which describes what is needed to reduce injustices in the world in<br />

which we live). 4 In several areas of the world, governmental agents<br />

are involved in the creation of (severe) economic <strong>and</strong> social injustice,<br />

either internationally or against some of its own minorities, or — in<br />

highly repressive states — against the vast majority of the population<br />

(e.g. Hochschild 1999; Roy 2014). <strong>The</strong> government is then more part of<br />

the problem than part of the solution, <strong>and</strong> some would argue that it<br />

is very naive to construct capabilitarian political theories that simply<br />

assume that the government will be a force for the good (Menon 2002).<br />

Similarly, some political philosophers have argued that in cases of<br />

injustice in which the government doesn’t take sufficient action, as in<br />

the case of harms done by climate change, duties fall on others who are<br />

in a position to ‘take up the slack’ or make a difference (Karnein 2014;<br />

Caney 2016).<br />

<strong>The</strong> third reason why capabilitarian political theories may not see<br />

the government as the only, or primary, agent of justice, relates to the<br />

question of how we decide to allocate the responsibility for being the<br />

agent of change. 5 As Monique Devaux points out, we can attribute<br />

moral <strong>and</strong> political agency derived from our responsibility in creating<br />

the injustice (a position advocated by Thomas Pogge (2008) in his work<br />

on global poverty) or because of the greater capacities <strong>and</strong> powers that<br />

3 For an introduction to the public choice literature, see Mueller (2003).<br />

4 On the distinction between ideal <strong>and</strong> non-ideal theories of justice, see e.g. Swift<br />

(2008); Stemplowska (2008); Robeyns (2008a); Valentini (2012).<br />

5 <strong>The</strong> second <strong>and</strong> third reasons may sometimes both be at work in an argument to<br />

attribute agency to a particular group or institutions.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!