06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

4. Critiques <strong>and</strong> Debates<br />

177<br />

But what about the philosophical theories of basic needs? Are there<br />

reasons why we should favour them rather than the capability approach?<br />

<strong>The</strong> arguments that were given for the pragmatic basic needs approach<br />

apply also to some extent to the questions of the complementarities<br />

<strong>and</strong> differences between the theories. <strong>The</strong>re are, theoretically, close<br />

similarities between theories of needs <strong>and</strong> capabilities, <strong>and</strong> Soran <strong>Re</strong>ader<br />

(2006) has argued that many of the objections that capability scholars<br />

have to theories of needs are unwarranted <strong>and</strong> based on implausibly<br />

reductionist readings of theories of needs. According to <strong>Re</strong>ader, theories<br />

of needs <strong>and</strong> capability theories have much more in common than<br />

capability scholars have been willing to see.<br />

Still, Sen has been notorious in arguing that the capability approach<br />

is superior to the basic needs approach, a critique he has reaffirmed<br />

in his latest book (Sen 2017, 25). In his paper ‘Goods <strong>and</strong> people’,<br />

Sen (1984a, 513–15) criticised the basic needs approach for being too<br />

focussed on commodities, <strong>and</strong> seeing human beings as passive <strong>and</strong><br />

needy. Those criticisms were rebutted by Alkire (2002, 166–74), who<br />

believed they were based on misinterpretations. However, Alkire did<br />

argue that the other two claims by Sen were correct. First, that the basic<br />

needs approach confines our attention to the most desperate situations,<br />

<strong>and</strong> is therefore only useful to developing countries. Alkire, however,<br />

sees this as potentially a strength of the basic needs approach; one<br />

could argue that it helps us to focus our attention on the worst off. Sen’s<br />

final criticism was, according to Alkire, the one with most theoretical<br />

bite: that the basic needs approach does not have solid philosophical<br />

foundations.<br />

However, the question is whether that is true. A set of recent<br />

papers by basic needs scholars (Brock <strong>and</strong> <strong>Re</strong>ader 2002; <strong>Re</strong>ader <strong>and</strong><br />

Brock 2004; <strong>Re</strong>ader 2006) make clear that the philosophical theory of<br />

basic needs is sophisticated; moreover, several philosophically highly<br />

sophisticated theories of needs have been proposed in the past, both<br />

in the Aristotelian tradition but also more recently by contemporary<br />

philosophers (e.g. Doyal <strong>and</strong> Gough 1991; Wiggins 1998). Instead, a<br />

more plausible explanation for the basic needs approach losing ground<br />

in comparison to the capability approach seems to me that in the case of<br />

the basic needs approach, there was less interaction between empirical<br />

scholars <strong>and</strong> policy makers on the one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> philosophers on<br />

the other. It is hard to find evidence of a clear synergy between basic

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!