06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

4. Critiques <strong>and</strong> Debates<br />

205<br />

(e.g. Gaertner <strong>and</strong> Xu 2006, 2008; Gotoh <strong>and</strong> Yoshihara 2003; Gotoh,<br />

Suzumura <strong>and</strong> Yoshihara 2005; Pattanaik 2006; Pattanaik <strong>and</strong> Xu 1990;<br />

Suzumura 2016; Xu 2002). Some reasons for this move are the same as the<br />

arguments against desire-satisfaction theories or the happiness approach<br />

that we reviewed earlier in sections 3.7 <strong>and</strong> 3.8. Another argument is<br />

that relevant information is left out of the informational basis. If two social<br />

states have exactly the same utility levels, but social state A has also<br />

a set of legal <strong>and</strong> social norms that discriminate against one group of<br />

people, whereas in social state B, the principles of moral equality <strong>and</strong><br />

non-discrimination are protected, then surely, we should prefer social<br />

state B over social state A. But welfarism, because of its exclusive focus<br />

on utilities, is unable to take any type of non-utility information into<br />

account, whether it is the violation of deontic principles, information on<br />

rights, liberties <strong>and</strong> justice, or information on inefficient or unsustainable<br />

use of common resources. Many of the welfare economists who have<br />

embarked on the development of a post-welfarist welfare economics<br />

have focussed on the importance of freedom as an important part of the<br />

widening of the informational basis.<br />

Non-welfarist welfare economics requires some changes to our<br />

approach to welfare economics. As Sen (1996, 58) noted in his discussion<br />

of the contribution of the capability approach to non-welfarist welfare<br />

economics, if we move to an informational basis with multiple<br />

dimensions of different types (as in the capability approach) then this<br />

requires explicit evaluations of the different weights to be given to the<br />

contributions of the different functionings <strong>and</strong> capabilities to overall<br />

(aggregate) social welfare. For Sen, the way to proceed is by public<br />

reasoning about those weights. This should probably not be seen as the<br />

only <strong>and</strong> exclusive way to determine them, since not all work in welfare<br />

economics is suited for public discussion — for example, it often entails<br />

desk-studies of inequalities or the analysis of the welfare effects of certain<br />

policy measures, <strong>and</strong> it is practically impossible to organise an exercise<br />

of public reasoning for every desk study that welfare economists make.<br />

Luckily, as the survey by Decancq <strong>and</strong> Lugo (2013) shows, there are<br />

various weighting systems possible that can give us the weights that are<br />

needed if one wants to aggregate the changes in different functionings<br />

<strong>and</strong> capabilities. For example, Erik Schokkaert (2007) has suggested that<br />

we derive the weights of the functionings from the contribution they

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!