06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2. Core Ideas <strong>and</strong> the Framework<br />

71<br />

part data-driven but in addition depend on some normative decision.<br />

Note that in the data-driven <strong>and</strong> hybrid approaches, the selection of<br />

dimensions <strong>and</strong> the weights tends to be done through a process in<br />

which the selection of dimensions <strong>and</strong> the determination of the weights<br />

go h<strong>and</strong> in h<strong>and</strong>. One example is the proposal by Erik Schokkaert<br />

(2007) of using happiness as the master-value by which we weigh the<br />

various capabilities that together form the multidimensional account of<br />

wellbeing. In this proposal, if the functionings do not contribute to one’s<br />

happiness, they are given a zero weight <strong>and</strong> hence no longer count in<br />

the wellbeing index. In methods such as this one, there are two rounds<br />

of the selections of the dimensions: the first before one collects the data,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the second when one uses econometric techniques to determine<br />

the contribution that the various functionings make to the master-value<br />

(here: life-satisfaction) <strong>and</strong> uses those as weights; those functionings<br />

that will make no contribution will receive a weight of zero, which is<br />

the same as being deleted as a dimension in the wellbeing index.<br />

Third, for non-empirical applications, we can categorize methods<br />

to determine weights in the same way as we could categorise methods<br />

for the selection of dimensions. Morten Fibieger Byskov (forthcoming)<br />

distinguishes between ad-hoc methods (such as the data-driven methods<br />

discussed by Decancq <strong>and</strong> Lugo), procedural methods, or foundational<br />

methods. A theoretical capability application could include answers to<br />

all B-modules (including the selection of dimensions) yet decide that<br />

the weighing of those dimensions should be done in a procedural way,<br />

e.g. via a democratic decision-making process. Alternatively, one could<br />

introduce one master-value that will determine which capabilities are<br />

relevant, <strong>and</strong> also what weights they should be given. One example is<br />

the empirical work done by Erik Schokkaert (2007), which was discussed<br />

above. Another example, which is theoretical, is Rutger Claassen’s<br />

capabilitarian theory of justice, in which the selection <strong>and</strong> weighing<br />

of capabilities is done based on their contribution to that person’s<br />

“navigational agency” (Claassen 2016).<br />

Note that in the case in which one has essentially a monistic theory<br />

in which there is a master-value, one may doubt whether this doesn’t<br />

violate property A7 from the A-module. At first value, it seems that it<br />

does. But proponents of a monistic theory may respond that all theories

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!