06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

174 <strong>Wellbeing</strong>, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Social</strong> <strong>Justice</strong><br />

applications, <strong>and</strong> (b) as far as those capability theories <strong>and</strong> applications<br />

are concerned, in favour of seriously considering procedural methods<br />

to decide which capabilities matter.<br />

However, even if we all accept that view, it doesn’t settle all disputes.<br />

Even if we agree that a selection of capabilities for, say, a poverty<br />

evaluation should differ from the selection of capabilities for a theory<br />

of justice, this still allows for different views on how that selection<br />

should be made. Some scholars have argued that it should be based on<br />

normative grounds, in other words based on philosophical reasoning<br />

<strong>and</strong> argumentation (Nussbaum 2000; 2006b; Claassen 2016). Others<br />

have argued for a selection based on a procedural method (Byskov<br />

2017). For empirical applications, it has been argued that the selection<br />

of dimensions should be made in a way that minimises biases in the<br />

selection (Robeyns 2003). For policy-relevant applications, it has been<br />

argued that the freedoms listed in the Universal Declaration of Human<br />

Rights could provide a good starting point, <strong>and</strong> should plausibly be<br />

playing a larger role in the selection of capabilities (Vizard 2007; Burchardt<br />

<strong>and</strong> Vizard 2011). <strong>The</strong>re are by now various overviews published on<br />

how to select functionings <strong>and</strong> capabilities but, interestingly, they<br />

almost always are limited to a certain type of capability theory, such<br />

as wellbeing for policy making (Hick <strong>and</strong> Burchardt 2016; Alkire 2016),<br />

multidimensional poverty measurement (Alkire 2016; Alkire et al.<br />

2015), human development projects <strong>and</strong> policies (Alkire 2002; Byskov<br />

forthcoming) <strong>and</strong> theories of justice (Robeyns 2016d). Thus, there are<br />

a range of arguments pointing out that the selection of capabilities for<br />

particular capability theories needs to be sensitive to the purpose of the<br />

theory in question, hence selection is a matter to be decided at the level<br />

of the individual capability theories, rather than at the more general <strong>and</strong><br />

abstract level of the capability approach (see also Sen 2004a).<br />

<br />

By introducing the concepts of ‘functionings’ <strong>and</strong> ‘capabilities’, the<br />

capability approach offers some specific notions of ‘advantage’ <strong>and</strong><br />

provides an ethical framework to guide our actions <strong>and</strong> institutional<br />

design. It is also a theoretical framework with clear commitments<br />

to practice <strong>and</strong> policy making in the world as it is, not just in some<br />

hypothetical world or in a stylized model. However, the same can be

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!