06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

3. Clarifications<br />

139<br />

work. She underst<strong>and</strong>s adaptive preferences as the preferences of<br />

people who do not want to have items of her list of capabilities, whereby<br />

these preferences are deformed due to injustices, oppression, ignorance<br />

<strong>and</strong> unreflective habit (Nussbaum 2000, 114).<br />

What questions do adaptive preferences raise for the capability<br />

approach? At the very minimum, they raise the following questions:<br />

first, why would adaptive preferences pose a problem for capability<br />

theories? Second, do we have any evidence about the prevalence of<br />

adaptive preferences? And third, how can capability scholars deal with<br />

adaptive preferences in their capability theories <strong>and</strong> applications?<br />

Let us start with the first of these questions: why would adaptive<br />

preferences pose a problem for capability theories? <strong>The</strong>re are at least<br />

two reasons. <strong>The</strong> first lies in module B2, the selection of dimensions. If<br />

that selection is done in a participatory or democratic way, then it may<br />

be vulnerable to adaptive preferences. A group that is systematically<br />

socialised to have low aspirations <strong>and</strong> ambitions will perhaps not put<br />

certain capabilities on its list, thereby telling themselves that they are<br />

unachievable, whereas objectively speaking they are achievable, albeit<br />

perhaps only after some social changes have taken place. <strong>The</strong> second<br />

reason is that a person with adaptive preferences may objectively have<br />

access to a certain capability, but may believe that either this capability<br />

is not available to her, or else that she should not choose it, <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

she may pick from her capabilities set a suboptimal combination of<br />

functionings. If we then assume that this person (or group) has nonadaptive<br />

preferences, then we will wrongly interpret the choice not<br />

to exercise certain capabilities as a matter of personal agency, which a<br />

capability theory that focusses on capabilities rather than functionings,<br />

should respect. <strong>The</strong> capability approach by default regards adults as<br />

agents rather than patients, but this may be problematic in the case of<br />

adaptive preferences.<br />

So we can conclude that adaptive preferences can pose a problem for<br />

capability theories in which the choice of dimensions is made democratic,<br />

or in which we focus on capabilities rather than functionings. But a critic<br />

may raise the question: do we have any evidence about the prevalence<br />

of adaptive preferences? Is this not a theoretical problem invented by<br />

philosophers who like complex puzzles, or by western scholars who<br />

pity the lives of poor people in the Global South?

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!