06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

58 <strong>Wellbeing</strong>, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Social</strong> <strong>Justice</strong><br />

such as the ontological idea that human beings are individuals who can<br />

live <strong>and</strong> flourish independently of others. However, there is no such<br />

claim in the principle of ethical individualism. <strong>The</strong> claim is rather one<br />

about whose interests should count. And ethical individualism claims<br />

that only the interests of persons should count. Ultimately, we care about<br />

each individual person. Ethical individualism forces us to make sure we<br />

ask questions about how the interests of each <strong>and</strong> every person are served or<br />

protected, rather than assuming that because, for example, all the other<br />

family members are doing fine, the daughter-in-law will be doing fine<br />

too. If, as all defensible moral theories do, we argue that every human<br />

being has equal moral worth, then we must attach value to the interests<br />

of each <strong>and</strong> every one of the affected persons. Thus, my first conclusion<br />

is that ethical individualism is a desirable property, since it is necessary<br />

to treat people as moral equals.<br />

But ethical individualism is not only a desirable property, it is also an<br />

unavoidable property. By its very nature the evaluation of functionings<br />

<strong>and</strong> capabilities is an evaluation of the wellbeing <strong>and</strong> freedom to achieve<br />

wellbeing of individual persons. Functionings are ‘beings’ <strong>and</strong> ‘doings’:<br />

these are dimensions of a human being, which is an embodied being,<br />

not merely a mind or a soul. And with the exception of the conjoined<br />

twins, <strong>and</strong> the case of the unborn child <strong>and</strong> the pregnant mother, bodies<br />

are physically separated from each other. 33 We are born as a human<br />

being with a body <strong>and</strong> future of her own, <strong>and</strong> we will die as a human<br />

being with a body <strong>and</strong> a past life narrative that is unique. This human<br />

being, that lives her life in an embodied way, thus has functionings that<br />

are related to her person, which is embodied. It is with the functionings<br />

<strong>and</strong> capabilities of these persons that the capability approach is<br />

concerned with. 34 However, as I will explain in detail in section 4.6,<br />

from this it does not follow that the capability approach conceptualises<br />

people in an atomistic fashion, <strong>and</strong> thus that the capability approach is<br />

‘individualistic’ — meant in a negative, pejorative way. And it also does<br />

not imply that a capabilitarian evaluation could not also evaluate the<br />

33 As Richardson (2016, 5) puts it, “all capabilities […] are dependent on the body.<br />

Without relying on one’s body there is nothing one can do or be”.<br />

34 Some have argued in favour of what they call ‘collective capabilities’, which I will<br />

discuss in section 3.6.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!