06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

162 <strong>Wellbeing</strong>, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Social</strong> <strong>Justice</strong><br />

human right. It has a much weaker moral urgency than the right to a fair<br />

trial, let alone the right to life. Human rights thus correspond to a subset<br />

of the domain of justice, <strong>and</strong> focus on those questions that are of utter<br />

importance, the protection of which should have a greater urgency than<br />

the support of other normative claims. <strong>The</strong> second threshold — social<br />

influenceability — implies that even if something valuable is hugely<br />

important, as long as there is no or very limited social influenceability,<br />

its protection cannot be a human right. For example, it makes no sense<br />

to speak of a human right to be protected from volcano eruptions, or<br />

a human right to be protected from cancer. However, one can say that<br />

there is a human right to be warned about volcano eruptions if the<br />

government has the relevant information. To the extent that there is<br />

more social influenceability, the scope to speak coherently of human<br />

rights increases.<br />

Human rights have corresponding duties. But on whom do those<br />

duties fall <strong>and</strong> what kind of duties are they? A broad, inclusive account<br />

of duties is given by Pablo Gilabert (2009, 673) who writes:<br />

[Human rights impose] a duty of the highest priority for individuals<br />

<strong>and</strong> governments to identify ways to protect certain important interests<br />

through (a) specific rights <strong>and</strong> entitlements, but also, when these<br />

are insufficient or not presently feasible, through (b) urgent goals of<br />

institution-building.<br />

Note that this definition does not limit the duty to protect human rights<br />

to governments only, <strong>and</strong> that it does include institution-building as an<br />

important path towards protecting human rights. 28<br />

<br />

<strong>The</strong> human rights literature is, just like the capability approach, deeply<br />

multidisciplinary <strong>and</strong> interdisciplinary. <strong>The</strong> philosophy of human rights<br />

“addresses questions about the existence, content, nature, universality,<br />

justification, <strong>and</strong> legal status of human rights” (Nickel 2014, 1). How<br />

can human rights exist in the first place? What should be the content of<br />

28 This relates to a complex discussion in legal <strong>and</strong> political philosophy on whether<br />

human rights can be protected by so-called ‘imperfect duties’ or ‘imperfect<br />

obligations’ which is beyond the scope of this book. See, amongst others, Polly<br />

Vizard (2006, 84–91) <strong>and</strong> Frances Kamm (2011) for further discussion.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!