06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

86 <strong>Wellbeing</strong>, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Social</strong> <strong>Justice</strong><br />

considerations in its evaluations, which are ‘borrowed’ from other<br />

approaches or theories. For example, the broader use of the capability<br />

approach often pays attention to other normative considerations<br />

<strong>and</strong> other values than only wellbeing, such as efficiency, agency, or<br />

procedural fairness.<br />

<strong>The</strong> broad view would, in most cases, have a more ambitious purpose<br />

for its use of the capability approach, such as societal evaluation or policy<br />

design. It would also have (either implicit or explicit) richer theories<br />

of human diversity, agency <strong>and</strong> structural constraints, <strong>and</strong> — most<br />

importantly — add several additional ontological <strong>and</strong> explanatory<br />

theories (module C1) <strong>and</strong> additional normative principles (module C4).<br />

<strong>The</strong> narrow view does not include modules C1 <strong>and</strong> C4, <strong>and</strong> this can<br />

make a huge difference to the kind of capability theory that emerges.<br />

An example of the broad view is David Crocker’s (2008) book on<br />

development ethics, in which he has extended the capability approach<br />

with accounts of agency, democratic deliberation <strong>and</strong> participation<br />

into a more detailed account of development ethics. Yet Crocker<br />

acknowledges that not all versions of the capability approach embrace<br />

agency so explicitly. <strong>The</strong> capability approach proper need not endorse<br />

a strong account of agency, but there are several scholars who have<br />

developed particular capability theories <strong>and</strong> applications in which<br />

agency plays a central role (e.g. Claassen <strong>and</strong> Düwell 2013; Claassen<br />

2016; Trommlerová, Klasen <strong>and</strong> Leßmann 2015).<br />

Why is this difference between the narrow <strong>and</strong> the broad uses of<br />

the capability approach relevant <strong>and</strong> important? <strong>The</strong>re are several<br />

important reasons. First, to assess a critique of the capability approach,<br />

we need to know whether the critique addresses the capability approach<br />

in its narrow use, or rather a specific version of its broad use. Second, we<br />

need to be clear that many of the additional normative commitments in<br />

the broad use of the capability approach are not essential to the capability<br />

approach: rather, they are optional choices made in modules B <strong>and</strong>,<br />

especially, module C1 (additional ontological <strong>and</strong> explanatory theories)<br />

<strong>and</strong> module C4 (additional normative principles <strong>and</strong> concerns). This<br />

insight will also be important when we address the question, in section<br />

4.9, of whether we can simply talk about ‘the capability approach’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘the human development paradigm’ as the same thing.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!