06.09.2021 Views

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

Wellbeing, Freedom and Social Justice The Capability Approach Re-Examined, 2017a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

42 <strong>Wellbeing</strong>, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Social</strong> <strong>Justice</strong><br />

punishment of the aggressor. If there is a set of social norms justifying<br />

rape, <strong>and</strong> would-be rapists help each other to be able to rape, then<br />

would-be rapists in that country effectively enjoy the capability to rape.<br />

But clearly, rape is a moral bad, <strong>and</strong> a huge harm to its victims; it is thus<br />

not a capability that a country should want to protect. This example<br />

illustrates that functionings as well as capabilities can be harmful or<br />

have a negative value, as well as be positive or valuable. At an abstract<br />

<strong>and</strong> general level, ‘functionings’ <strong>and</strong> ‘capabilities’ are thus in themselves<br />

neutral concepts, <strong>and</strong> hence we cannot escape the imperative to decide<br />

which ones we want to support <strong>and</strong> enable, <strong>and</strong> which ones we want to<br />

fight or eliminate. Frances Stewart <strong>and</strong> Séverine Deneulin (2002, 67) put<br />

it as follows:<br />

[…] some capabilities have negative values (e.g. committing murder),<br />

while others may be trivial (riding a one-wheeled bicycle). Hence there is<br />

a need to differentiate between ‘valuable’ <strong>and</strong> non-valuable capabilities,<br />

<strong>and</strong> indeed, within the latter, between those that are positive but of lesser<br />

importance <strong>and</strong> those that actually have negative value.<br />

<strong>The</strong> above examples show that some functionings can be unequivocally<br />

good (e.g. being in good health) or unequivocally bad (e.g. being<br />

raped or being murdered). In those cases, there will be unanimity on<br />

whether the functionings outcome is bad or good. But now we need to<br />

add a layer of complexity. Sometimes, it will be a matter of doubt, or of<br />

dispute, whether a functioning will be good or bad — or the goodness<br />

or badness may depend on the context <strong>and</strong>/or the normative theory we<br />

endorse. An interesting example is giving care, or ‘care work’. 22 Clearly<br />

being able to care for someone could be considered a valuable capability.<br />

For example, in the case of child care, there is much joy to be gained, <strong>and</strong><br />

many parents would like to work less so as to spend more time with<br />

their children. But care work has a very ambiguous character if we try<br />

to answer whether it should be considered to be a valuable functioning<br />

from the perspective of the person who does the care. Lots of care is<br />

performed primarily because there is familial or social pressure put on<br />

someone (generally women) to do so, or because no-one else is doing it<br />

22 On the complex nature of ‘care’, <strong>and</strong> what the need to care <strong>and</strong> be cared for requires<br />

from a just society, see e.g. Tronto (1987); Kittay (1999); Nussbaum (2006b); Folbre<br />

(1994); Folbre <strong>and</strong> Bittman (2004); Engster (2007); Gheaus (2011); Gheaus <strong>and</strong><br />

Robeyns (2011).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!