13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Grounded Action: <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> against Skepticism<br />

Edward Guetti, Seton Hall University, USA<br />

I am sitting with a philosopher in the garden; he says<br />

again and again “I know that that’s a tree,” pointing to a<br />

tree that is near us. Someone else arrives and hears<br />

this, and I tell him: “This fellow isn’t insane. We are only<br />

doing philosophy.” 1<br />

An impassable divide between our everyday experiences<br />

and our ideals seems to be an indelible aspect of the<br />

human experience. How do I know that this is the good<br />

life, how do I even know that I am the being that I think I<br />

am? Skepticism has always thrived on this professed riff.<br />

Any attempt that recognized the riff and attempted to<br />

bridge it was doomed to deconstruction from the outset.<br />

Philosophical skeptics, following Descartes’ example, have<br />

understood their aim as infecting even the most “ordinary”<br />

propositions with skeptical doubt. This position has<br />

evolved into the more radical claim that not only can we<br />

not be certain of any of our claims to knowledge, but no<br />

certainty or knowledge exists even in the language in<br />

which we express our knowledge claims. Such a skeptical<br />

claim rests on a peculiar understanding of language -an<br />

understanding which has completely ignored the<br />

contributions of <strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>. When we begin to<br />

investigate how language works we discover that there is<br />

no need to bridge the riff off of which skeptics have<br />

profited, as no riff necessarily exists!<br />

What separates the responses of <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, and<br />

even Quine to a large degree, from other language-based<br />

responses to skepticism is precisely their understanding of<br />

language as the performance of games which are couched<br />

in a number of contexts. Denying our ability to be certain of<br />

the meaning of our speech, and hence, our thought,<br />

requires much more than what the skeptic would have us<br />

believe.<br />

Thomas Nagel in his The View from Nowhere and<br />

Peter Unger in his “A Defense of Skepticism” 2 both<br />

respond to a challenge issued by recent (ca. 1950)<br />

criticisms made by philosophers of language against a<br />

skeptical attitude. Nagel rightly claims that “recently there<br />

has been a revival of arguments against the possibility of<br />

skepticism reminiscent of the ordinary language arguments<br />

of the fifties” (L&M, 82-83) and goes on to formulate a welldefended<br />

skeptical posture against said language-based<br />

responses. However the argument chosen as the<br />

response of philosophers of language by Nagel and<br />

(though tacitly) Unger is quite certainly not the best<br />

response.<br />

Nagel’s skepticism relies on the realist conception of<br />

language: “What we refer to by the terms in our statements<br />

about the external world […] is said to be whatever actually<br />

bears the appropriate relation to the generally accepted<br />

use of those terms in our language. (This relation is left<br />

undefined, but it is supposed to be exemplified in the<br />

ordinary world by the relation between my use of the word<br />

“tree” and actual trees, if there are such things.)” (L&M, 83)<br />

Nagel goes on to insert his skeptical wedge between what<br />

we intend to signify and the signifier which we use: “Such<br />

[language-based responses to skepticism] are refuted by<br />

the evident possibility and intelligibility of skepticism, which<br />

1 <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, On Certainty, #467<br />

2 Both articles are presented here as they are found in Landesman and<br />

Meeks, 2003, henceforth (L&M).<br />

reveals that by ‘tree’ I don’t mean just anything that is<br />

causally responsible for my impressions of trees, or<br />

anything that looks and feels like a tree, or even anything<br />

of the sort that I and others have traditionally called trees.<br />

Since those things could conceivably not be trees, any<br />

theory that says they have to be is wrong.” (L&M, 84)<br />

Nagel concludes that there can be no assured certainty<br />

that the words I use are meaningful or accurately describe<br />

what it is I wish to describe.<br />

Unger as well bases his response on such an<br />

understanding: he believes that what he calls “basic<br />

absolute terms” (words like “flat”, “certain”, etc.) have no<br />

place in our speech, and hence our knowledge, because<br />

one hardly ever is referencing something which is, e.g.,<br />

absolutely flat (L&M, 91-92). Unger requires a bit more<br />

than Nagel, not only does he demand that words operate<br />

on a empirically testable one-to-one correspondence with<br />

the world, but the meaning of a word is to be organized<br />

into a one-to-one relation with the word itself. This can be<br />

seen from the disturbing feeling Unger expresses when he<br />

observes that absolute terms can on occasion also admit<br />

degrees of relative (i.e. contextual) meaning. It is rather<br />

obvious at this point that this referential conception of<br />

language to which both Unger and Nagel respond is no<br />

match even for any lightweight version of skepticism. To<br />

what, then, should we turn to put our skeptical worries to<br />

rest if not a referential theory of meaning?<br />

It is precisely a contextual theory of meaning that<br />

will help us put our skeptical doubts to rest. This<br />

contextualism, however, goes well beyond understanding<br />

where and by whom a statement is made but how we use<br />

different statements will determine meaning (as<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> has remarked: “it is only in use that the<br />

proposition has its sense.” On Certainty 3 , #10). In using<br />

words meaningfully we exhibit our grasp of them and<br />

consequently our knowledge or certainty of their meaning.<br />

Certainty moves from being an inner, mental state to being<br />

part of an expression, something outside of one’s own<br />

mind. A fundamental tenet of both Quine’s and<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s view is that any empirical statement about<br />

the world is misleading in its apparent simplicity (i.e. that it<br />

can be judged as either agreeing or disagreeing with ‘the<br />

facts’). For Quine empirical propositions are not only<br />

“couched” in networks of other beliefs, but “the total field<br />

[of our beliefs] is so underdetermined by its boundary<br />

conditions, experience, that there is much latitude of<br />

choice as to what statements to re-evaluate in the light of<br />

any single contrary experience.” (L&M, 325) Our network<br />

of beliefs only interact with experience on their periphery<br />

and so empirical observations not only reflect something<br />

exterior to ourselves but also, to a greater degree, reflect<br />

greater aspects of our networks of belief. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

makes many similar points throughout On Certainty, e.g. a<br />

statement about the date of a battle Napoleon fought in<br />

also implies that the earth existed at that date, that there<br />

were people other than Napoleon, etc. “When we first<br />

begin to believe anything, what we believe is not a single<br />

proposition, it is a whole system of propositions. (Light<br />

dawns gradually over the whole.)” (OC, #141) If empirical<br />

statements are misleading in their simplicity, if our<br />

experiences affect our beliefs, they are only the inch or so<br />

3 Henceforth (OC).<br />

113

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!