13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Rule following and intercultural perspective<br />

Michał Sala, Warsaw University, Poland<br />

This paper appears in the context of last year's Christoph<br />

Durt's paper discussing <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s intercultural<br />

approach to philosophy (Durt, 2005). Ending the<br />

discussion of it, he expressed a belief, that there is a<br />

possibility of creating a “bridging” perspective between two<br />

cultures (two forms of life). This suggestion encouraged<br />

me to investigate, how such a belief is grounded in<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s framework.<br />

The direction my investigation is bound is towards a<br />

well known problem of translation. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s account<br />

of language brings into focus the fact, that a language is a<br />

part of social practice. As he puts it, a sentence of our<br />

language is a move in our language game. (PI, par. 22).<br />

Apart from our utterances, our language involves<br />

behaviour, our form of life. Thus, understanding a<br />

language, understanding it's sentences involves<br />

participating in a form of life this language is a part of.<br />

A brief sketch like that, suggests that if we do not<br />

participate in a given form of life, we are unable to achieve<br />

understanding of a language with is involved in it. Thus,<br />

speakers of English cannot understand the meanings of,<br />

say, Swahili speakers unless they are able to participate in<br />

their form of life.<br />

The point of Durt's paper was to say, that we can,<br />

according to <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, bridge the distance between<br />

cultures, between different forms of life, and moreover, we<br />

should treat is as our methodology in philosophy. What he<br />

calls ethnological approach allows us to find connecting<br />

links (Zwieschenglieder), and establish an understanding<br />

of other culture from an outsider point of view. Of course,<br />

we are not an outsider any more – we now share other<br />

culture's form of life while not losing a hold on our own.<br />

Our perspective is not that of our original culture, though,<br />

and not that of an researched one. Nevertheless, if we are<br />

to comprehend other cultures, this is the only perspective<br />

we can achieve – stepping outside of our own tight shoes<br />

towards something we can have in common with our<br />

subject of inquiry.<br />

Language, rules and forms of life<br />

The point of this paper, however, is not to pursue the<br />

direction showed by Durt's reading of Remarks on Fraser's<br />

“Golden Bough”. My intention is to shed some light on how<br />

these connecting links are possible at all.<br />

Numerous remarks in Philosophical Investigations<br />

and Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics explore<br />

sceptical intuitions about “following a rule”. Following a rule<br />

is essential to any type of social practice that <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

wrote about (and probably to any kind of practice), be it<br />

mathematics, language games or plain games (like chess).<br />

The only way we could make sense of our participation in<br />

social practice is if we cast our doubts about following a<br />

rule away, at least on practical grounds. Following a rule is<br />

knowing a rule, and achieving a result this rule is meant to<br />

achieve.<br />

Suppose we want to teach someone a game we<br />

know. There are different types of games, and different<br />

types of rules they are guided by. There may be formal<br />

rules (like types of valid moves in chess) or informal rules<br />

(like tactics). Teaching a game involves either explaining<br />

its rules (using a language) or showing the practice of our<br />

game. Neither the former nor the latter guarantees our<br />

student will 'grasp' what we intend, though. Even if he<br />

behaves properly in all the situations we have shown (or<br />

described) him, we cannot be sure, that he fails to do so in<br />

any new situation that is a part of our game (and implicite<br />

governed by our rules).<br />

The ability to grasp and act accordingly to rules<br />

must be assumed if we want any type of social practice to<br />

be possible. Specifically, we need that kind of ability to be<br />

able to teach someone (even belonging to our own culture,<br />

sharing our form of life) to use a language. In a vast<br />

number of cases, we cannot do anything better than to<br />

count on their 'grasping' our intention. But given that it is<br />

possible that they can (at least in practice) do that, allows<br />

us to teach them games, including language games. As<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s remarks on mathematics show, the result of<br />

student's practice is a proof of him understanding the rule,<br />

although not impossible revise.<br />

If we are able to teach people sharing our form of<br />

life a language we know, then we do have the ability to<br />

'grasp' rules.<br />

Given that, we should consider learning a different<br />

form of life.<br />

Forms of life<br />

What are forms of life? As Durt suggests, we should think<br />

about them as cultures, as our language (probably, but<br />

that generates problems with considerations from the<br />

previous section), our beliefs and social practices we, as a<br />

culture, share. So, assuming that we can teach someone a<br />

language, the question about teaching a form of life is a<br />

question whether we can teach someone our beliefs and<br />

practices.<br />

If we assume that we can teach someone a<br />

language, then teaching them our beliefs should be trivial.<br />

Teaching them our practice involves the same type of<br />

'grasping' our intentions as teaching a language does. Our<br />

problem, though, seems trivial only when we've forgotten<br />

about assumption, that we already share a form of life, that<br />

we've taken in the previous paragraph.<br />

Consider forms of life, then. We can think about<br />

animals or aliens having other forms of life than us. Let us<br />

assume that we consider only human forms of life. If we<br />

have a language, it has to be possible to think of. If we<br />

have certain beliefs, they have to make sense in our<br />

language. If we share some social practices, they must be<br />

possible to be grasped by another member of our society –<br />

and another human. If we wish to say, that essentially all<br />

humans share the same kind of ability to grasp rules, then<br />

it follows, that in theory, any given human should be able<br />

to grasp any kind of a rule. Since our learning rules of the<br />

games bases on 'grasping' them, then nothing holds us<br />

from saying, that we can learn any social practice<br />

whatever it be, since it bases on the same notion of rules<br />

as games do.<br />

287

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!