13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

the possibility of defending the cartoons as works of art.<br />

Surely, their aesthetic quality is minimal. If it were high, it<br />

could outweigh minor moral objections, making them<br />

morally tolerable.<br />

More to the point, of course, is freedom of the press,<br />

partly subsumable under freedom of expression. Yet, it<br />

possesses special features and is associated with special<br />

obligations, articulaed in the many professional codes of<br />

ethics of journalists. I distinguish between the decision to<br />

publish the cartoons in the first place and decisions to<br />

republish them. Jyllands-Posten published the cartoons<br />

after illustrators had refused to contribute to a book on the<br />

Koran and Muhammad or at least wanted to remain<br />

anonymous, for fear of Muslim retaliation, and after this<br />

matter had been reported in the Danish press. Angered by<br />

this, the editors of Jyllands-Posten wanted to show<br />

courage (required by those codes) and test the exercise of<br />

free speech in Denmark. They could not foresee the<br />

reactions abroad. Had they known them, they said, they<br />

would not have published the cartoons. This concession,<br />

surely, is rather prudential than purely moral.<br />

Decisions to republish the cartoons form a mixed<br />

affair. They might be inspired by the same motives as<br />

those of Jyllands-Posten. But they can also be seen as<br />

exercises of the right and duty to inform the public<br />

truthfully, adequately and comprehensively about a<br />

controversy. Muslim circles, of course, have seen them as<br />

insult piled on insult.<br />

4. Morality in a Messy World<br />

Violence, threat or manipulation has no place or role<br />

in morality as such. If someone offended someone else,<br />

then, from the moral point of view, the offended one may<br />

express his anger in a non-violent form, the offender<br />

should offer his sincere excuses, possibly mitigated in the<br />

case of an unintentional offense, will often promise not to<br />

repeat his misconduct and think of some additional ways<br />

of making repair. Yet, in reality, offenses frequently lead to<br />

verbal fights and more. The straightforward moral point of<br />

view gets obstructed by thoughts and acts of aggression,<br />

resentment, revenge, strategic manipulation and also of<br />

self-defense and self-protection, depending on the<br />

circumstances. It is not that ethics has nothing to say<br />

about situations where things get out of hand. For fights of<br />

a greater dimension, for example, there after all are the<br />

well worked-out Principles of Just War. In all such<br />

situations, there is the general moral duty to restore peace<br />

and security. Legal systems and international treaties – in<br />

the example given, the Geneva Conventions – are meant<br />

to bring some order into the messy human world. One,<br />

then, has the second-order moral duty to heed the law and<br />

agreements.<br />

The circumstances that go to explain the reactions<br />

in the cartoon controversy are too many and too complex<br />

to be detailed here (cf. Bednarz et al. <strong>2006</strong>). There is the<br />

long history of enmity between Islam and Christianity. The<br />

Muslim world and culture lost the superiority they once<br />

possessed. Many Muslims now feel exploited, excluded,<br />

humiliated, misunderstood or despised by the West. And<br />

since 9/11 Muslims have felt subject to a generalized<br />

suspicion of being potential terrorists. Given such feelings,<br />

it was easy for religious and political leaders to organize<br />

mass protests and boycotts, and let violent reactions to the<br />

Danish cartoons happen – maybe welcome distractions<br />

from their own problems at home. Acts of destruction and<br />

incitements to kill the cartoonists, of course, are morally<br />

unacceptable.<br />

Reflections on Ethics and Cultural Clash - Peter P. Kirschenmann<br />

What about the circumstances in Western<br />

countries? The invited cartoonists who refused to<br />

contribute or wanted to stay anonymous remembered that<br />

all Muslims were called upon to kill Salman Rushdie and<br />

knew about the actual murder of Theo van Gogh. The<br />

“courage” shown by the editors of Jyllands-Posten could<br />

be considered to be misplaced. The substantial issue, also<br />

in most of the commentaries, has been whether, or in how<br />

much, we should sacrifice freedom of speech to Muslim<br />

threats and violent actions. If we did so at all, in a<br />

reconciliatory mood, due to non-ethical motives, we would<br />

at least lose some of our moral integrity and maybe much<br />

more. If we did not, politicians might fear that we would<br />

endanger the flow of oil from Arab countries.<br />

One commentator (Black <strong>2006</strong>) says to be furious<br />

about any attempts to placate Muslim demonstrators,<br />

“understand” their anger. Her main argument is that they<br />

should not complain, since they have been doing the same<br />

thing with their anti-Semitic cartoons and their anti-Semitic<br />

and anti-American propaganda. Such a very common tu<br />

quoque argument has little to do with morality: it does not<br />

ask what is right, but denies the opposing party the<br />

relevant moral standing for complaining. It is a<br />

confrontational strategic move, though, to me, an ethically<br />

permissible one. A. Hirsi Ali (<strong>2006</strong>), who had to go into<br />

hiding because of death threats, has, in her political and<br />

cinematographic work, been emphatically pleading for<br />

abandoning a policy of reconciliation in favor of a policy of<br />

confrontation with respect to radical fundamentalist<br />

Muslims, from whom more moderate Muslims, in her mind,<br />

too little distantiate themselves. She reminds us of<br />

Chamberlain’s policy and its consequences, replaced then<br />

by Churchill’s. In a confrontational approach, morality will<br />

often be moved to the back seat, except for the<br />

assessment of the envisioned goal.<br />

5. Concluding Remarks<br />

Europe had to go through long periods of atrocious and, in<br />

large part, senseless religious wars before the principles of<br />

religious freedom and tolerance were formulated and<br />

accepted. In many countries, revolutions and violent<br />

struggles were needed to establish or enforce civil rights<br />

and liberties, among which free speech; at times, nonviolent<br />

movements have been successful. It is not<br />

predictable which course Islamic countries will take in<br />

these respects. Some, like S. P. Huntington (1996), think<br />

that world politics is entering a phase in which clashes, not<br />

so much between nations, but between cultures, most of<br />

which religion-based, will be inevitable. Even if one does<br />

not share this view, it is certainly not enough just to hope<br />

that conflicts will disappear.<br />

No ethical theory tells us to condone oppression or<br />

terror. Thus, one should strive, as suggested by Oomen, to<br />

realize liveable local arrangements, morally and otherwise<br />

acceptable, as much as possible honoring human rights.<br />

Historical and current experience, though, warns us that<br />

changing a totalitarian religious order too rapidly, may<br />

cause more pain than positive results. One should also<br />

work towards a global order which incorporates at least<br />

minimal moral standards. On both fronts, negotiation and<br />

dialogue will be needed. Yet, these cannot get underway<br />

in a civilized form, as long as the circumstances, as<br />

sketched above, have not suitably changed.<br />

For judging cultures and intercultural transactions,<br />

H. Procee (1991) formulated two ethical meta-principles,<br />

those of non-exclusion and of promotion of interaction.<br />

“The first demands respect and some protection of other<br />

145

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!