13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Our thesis is that the dichotomy between the Realist<br />

and the Constructivist views which dominates the modern<br />

philosophy of mathematics is misleading. With time not<br />

only the doctrines but also what is considered as the<br />

opposites change.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s approach is in a way transversal to<br />

both. What is essential to <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s philosophy of<br />

mathematics is that philosophy is a descriptive activity. So<br />

the aim of the philosopher of mathematics is to understand<br />

mathematics as it is. It is no part of the philosopher’s task<br />

to rewrite all or part of mathematics in new and better<br />

ways. The philosopher wants to describe mathematics, but<br />

needs to be careful to separate mathematics itself from the<br />

philosophy of mathematics.<br />

For <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> philosophy and mathematics have<br />

nothing to say to one another. It would seem that no<br />

philosophical opinion could affect the procedures of the<br />

mathematicians.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> saw the distinction between<br />

mathematics itself, on one hand and what is said about<br />

mathematics, on the other, as being of fundamental<br />

philosophical importance.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> asserts in “Philosophical<br />

Investigations” (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1956) that there are no<br />

mathematical propositions or truths.<br />

Mathematics has its foundation in the activity of<br />

calculating.<br />

Thus for <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> an empirical regularity lies<br />

behind a mathematical law.<br />

The mathematical law does not assert what the<br />

regularity obtains.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> claims that what we are doing in<br />

mathematics is calculation. If we do not prove anything in<br />

logical sense, so no possibility of producing a logical<br />

contradiction does arise. It means that a calculus is<br />

consistent if we calculate in it. Indeed, no proof could tell<br />

us that “this calculus is inconsistent or consistent”,<br />

because there is no calculus which itself can prove<br />

anything.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> emphasizes that the calculi which<br />

make up mathematics are extremely diverse and<br />

heterogeneous – what he calls the “motley” mathematics.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> insists that to accept a theorem is to<br />

adopt a new rule of language. It follows from the statement<br />

that our concepts cannot remain unchanged at the end of<br />

the proof. For an intuitionist, every natural number is either<br />

prime or composite. So we have a method for deciding<br />

whether this number is prime or not. But <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

argues that we do not have reliable method even to<br />

construct the numbers.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s main reason for denying the<br />

objectivity of mathematical truth is his denial of the<br />

objectivity of proof in mathematics, his idea is that a proof<br />

does not compel acceptance.<br />

This idea is closely connected with <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s<br />

doctrine that the meaning is the use.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s constructivism is seen as a much<br />

more restricted kind than Brouwer’s intuitionism.<br />

It seems that <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> is a strict finitist, because<br />

he held that the only comprehensible and valid kind of<br />

proof in mathematics takes the form of intuitively clear<br />

manipulations with concrete objects.<br />

18<br />

About <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s mathematical epistemology - Olga Antonova / Sergei Soloviev<br />

Developing further Brouwer’s views Heyting asserts<br />

(cf. Heyting 1974) that proofs are mental constructions with<br />

fulfilments of intensions.<br />

Heyting explained mathematical propositions as<br />

expressions of intentions, «intensions» none only refer to<br />

the states of affairs thought to exist independently of us<br />

but also to the experiences thought to be possible.<br />

Martin-Löf’s views in this are similar to Heyting’s.<br />

Martin-Löf asserts that a proof is not an object, but<br />

an act, (cf. Martin-Löf, 1996).<br />

So a proof is a cognitive act or a process before it is<br />

an object, an act or a process in which we come to see or<br />

grasp something intuitively.<br />

Also Martin-Löf’s system of intuitionistic type theory<br />

uses four basic forms of judgment, among which are the<br />

two that «S is a proposition» and «a is a proof<br />

(construction) of the proposition S». Martin-Löf notes that<br />

we can read these, equivalently, as «S is an intention» and<br />

«a is a method of fulfilling the intention S». Thus, we can<br />

understand his system as a formalization of the informal<br />

concepts of intentionality, intuition and evidence.<br />

Let us now turn briefly to Dummett’s views, because<br />

Dummett has a very original and interesting view on<br />

problems of the philosophical basis of proof.<br />

Dummett, who agrees with <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> on the role<br />

of language in mathematics, believes there is no way to<br />

approach the question about proof independently of<br />

investigation in the philosophy of language.<br />

Dummett contrasts his view with the position that<br />

the meaning of proposition is determined by its truth<br />

conditions.<br />

For Dummett only the use of language determines<br />

the meaning of an individual statement. One of the things<br />

that disappears with the idea of mental acts and processes<br />

in Dummett’s approach is the philosophical objection to the<br />

form of intuitionism based on solipsism. But we shall argue<br />

that Dummett goes too far here. Dummett’s account of<br />

intuitionism contains no theory of intentionality, fulfilled<br />

intentions and evidence. He suggests no theory of<br />

mathematicians as cognitive information “processors”, the<br />

cognitive structure of mental acts and meaning of mental<br />

representations and the like. We think that if the proof is<br />

really to be understood as either a cognitive act or as an<br />

objectification of an act then these notions must figure in<br />

our understanding of the philosophical basis of intuition.<br />

Thus it is clear that the philosophical basis of<br />

intuitionistic mathematics is best understood along the<br />

lines suggested by Heyting’s investigations. So according<br />

to the views of intuitionists, the main source of intuitionistic<br />

mathematics and criterion of the validity of its constructions<br />

is intuition. Conclusions of intuitionistic mathematics are<br />

not obtained by precisely established rules which could be<br />

united in a logical system. On the contrary evidence of any<br />

separate conclusion is considered directly. The essence of<br />

the mathematical proof consists not in logical conclusions<br />

and in design of mathematical systems. It is obvious that<br />

mathematical activity is defined not with language and<br />

logic but as constructive activity of pure thinking.<br />

Proceeding from the position that the intuitionistic<br />

mathematics is a mental process, obviously, any language<br />

including the language of formalization cannot be an<br />

equivalent model of the given system as the thinking<br />

cannot be reduced to a finite number of formal rules. Logic<br />

is only a true imitation of mathematical language. Logic

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!