13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Both notions have been criticised as being speculative, but<br />

in neither case this criticism is justified.<br />

Yet, there is also a striking difference between<br />

Anscombe and von Wright concerning the nature of this<br />

more basic dependency concept: for Anscombe the<br />

difference between observing and intervening plays no<br />

role, but for von Wright it is crucial. I believe that when we<br />

turn to <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, this difference may be cleared up.<br />

3. Reacting to the cause<br />

In his manuscript, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> takes issue with a paper by<br />

Russell (Russell 1936), who argues that before we come<br />

to know a cause by experiencing regularities we must first<br />

know it by intuition. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> objects to this idea of<br />

knowledge by intuition. Instead, he points our attention to<br />

the practice of reacting to the cause. In some cases we<br />

react instinctively or non-consciously to some external<br />

stimulus, e.g., blushing or moving nervously when<br />

someone is staring at us. This is a form of reacting to the<br />

cause, although there is no mediating `intuitive<br />

awareness'. In this context, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> quotes Goethe,<br />

``im Anfang war die Tat''.<br />

The origin and the primitive form of the language game<br />

is a reaction; only from this can more complicated forms<br />

develop. (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1976, p. 420)<br />

There are many forms of reacting, not all of which<br />

are immediate. In such cases we speak of `looking for the<br />

cause'. Here, again, there are different types. In one type<br />

of case, we simply trace the cause, e.g., tracing a moving<br />

rope to find the person pulling at it. Upon finding this<br />

person pulling the rope, reacting to the cause (i.e., to him)<br />

is simply a response, e.g., to stop the rope from moving.<br />

This reaction need not be construed as the overcoming of<br />

doubt or the inference ``that this is the cause of the<br />

movement of the rope''. The second type of case is where<br />

we do not simply trace the cause, but perform experiments<br />

to find the cause.<br />

In one case “He is the cause” simply means: he pulled<br />

the string. In the other case it means roughly: those are<br />

the conditions that I would have to change in order to get<br />

rid of this phenomenon. (idem, p. 417)<br />

In R. Rhees' lecture notes (p. 433) we find that<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> claims that it is their common function of<br />

predicting what will happen which explains why we use this<br />

one word `cause' in both cases. That is not to say that they<br />

always give us the same results. We may find by<br />

experiment that the cause is something other than the<br />

thing to which we instinctively react. But the practice of<br />

looking for a cause is one root of the ``cause-effect<br />

language-game'' and this explains the use of this word for<br />

both types of behavior.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s analysis of causation is more diverse<br />

than what is presented by Anscombe and von Wright.<br />

Anscombe focusses on the reaction of looking from one<br />

thing to another thing: when one billiard ball launches<br />

another, our reaction to the cause (the hitting) is that we<br />

look at the effect (the movement of the second ball).<br />

Though her views are not couched in terms of reactions,<br />

they no doubt closely resemble what <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> writes<br />

about tracing the cause.<br />

Von Wright accepts the traditional view in which<br />

causation is lawlike and nomic, but the reason for this may<br />

simply be that he is concerned with the issue of scientific<br />

methodology. In natural science we try to discover and<br />

Derivativeness, production and reacting to the cause - Rosja Mastop<br />

explain regularities by means of experiment. As<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s analysis shows, there is no conflict between<br />

the existence of this practice and the existence of the<br />

practice of tracing causes (this does not exclude the<br />

possibility of a conflict between the findings of either<br />

practice). Von Wright is only concerned with the latter<br />

practice---he explicitly refers to the concept he is interested<br />

in as `experimentalist causation'---and so for him the<br />

conceptual connection between causation and regularity is<br />

not unreasonable. In this respect, the differences between<br />

Anscombe and von Wright in this respect could almost be<br />

terminological: for which practice do we reserve the term<br />

`cause'?<br />

Von Wright directs our attention to the agency<br />

involved in performing experiments. He argues that this<br />

practice is constitutive of our understanding of causal<br />

connections as being nomic. Although this element in von<br />

Wright's work is commonly interpreted as an influence of<br />

Collingwood, it also clearly follows on <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>'s<br />

analysis. Looking for the cause is of course more than a<br />

mere shift of attention. We aim to impute the witnessed<br />

event to something or someone, or we aim to guard<br />

ourselves against something, or, indeed, we aim to<br />

intervene in the mechanism to change the course of<br />

events. We look for a cause in order to intervene.<br />

Consequently, without the idea of being able to intervene<br />

we cannot make sense of the practice of looking for the<br />

cause.<br />

Von Wright then takes the analysis one step further.<br />

He notes that tracing an event, qua action, to a person is<br />

different from tracing it to, say, a cogwheel or a virus.<br />

Looking for the cause is a process that can, in principle, be<br />

continued indefinitely. But when we impute responsibility to<br />

a person, the tracing comes to an end. This is so, not<br />

because the agent is an `unmoved mover', a view to which<br />

von Wright objects, but because holding a person<br />

responsible is not the same as tracing the behavior to<br />

some cortical activity. The reactions following imputation<br />

are different from the reactions upon finding a cause. In<br />

the latter case we may either restart the activity of tracing<br />

the cause anew, or physically intervene in the mechanism.<br />

In the former case, on the other hand, we can ask for the<br />

person's motives and reason with him. In doing so, we are<br />

not tracing the behavior to some preceding event, but we<br />

consider the person capable of intentional action and we<br />

are generally satisfied when the motivation strikes us as<br />

reasonable or natural. However, giving a motivation<br />

presupposes the capability to do otherwise. We do not<br />

trace the behavior from the person to his motives, but the<br />

motives are attributed to him. In view of this, the attribution<br />

of responsibility can give us the idea of alternative futures<br />

which the notion of tracing a cause in principle does not.<br />

This further step is, I take it, still understandable as<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>ian. In fact, von Wright quotes <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> in<br />

a footnote on this point:<br />

An intention is embedded in its situation, in human<br />

customs and institutions. (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1953, sect. 337)<br />

This is for von Wright the source for his view that<br />

explanation in the social sciences is different from<br />

explanation in the natural sciences, and that the latter<br />

practice depends on the very same customs and<br />

institutions as the former does.<br />

187

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!