13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Do We Really Need Relativism About Truth?<br />

Julien Murzi, University of Rome “La Sapienza”, Italy and<br />

University of Saint Andrews, UK<br />

1. MacFarlane on Relative Truth<br />

Philosophy is confronted with relativism at least since<br />

Protagoras’ most famous dictum: man is measure of<br />

everything. Contemporary relativists typically do not deny<br />

that, within certain areas of discourse, truth can be<br />

objective. Rather, they wonder whether in all discourses<br />

truth should be objective. Their answer is: “No”. The paper<br />

focuses on John MacFarlane’s and Max Kölbel’s recent<br />

relativistic frameworks and argues that they run into<br />

serious objections.<br />

According to MacFarlane, truth is to be conceived<br />

as relative at least within the three following discourses:<br />

future contingents, epistemic modalities and knowledge<br />

attributions. Consider future contingents (MacFarlane<br />

2003). My friend Joe utters at time t0:<br />

210<br />

(1) There will be a sea battle tomorrow.<br />

Unless we are determinist, as uttered at time t0, (1)<br />

is arguably neither true nor false. Call this the<br />

indeterminacy intuition. Now assume that (1)’s truthconditions<br />

are satisfied at a time t1 > t0: in fact, a sea battle<br />

occurs at the time predicted by Joe. Hence, it seems, Joe’s<br />

utterance was already true at t0. Call this the determinacy<br />

intuition. Of course, according to standard semantics, the<br />

two intuitions should be mutually exclusive. For the very<br />

same (proposition expressed by the very same) utterance<br />

cannot have different truth-values. However, MacFarlane<br />

suggests, both intuitions are correct, and should therefore<br />

be respected. Standard semantics, it follows, is to be given<br />

up: truth is to be thought as relative both to a context of<br />

utterance and a context of assessment.<br />

Consider now epistemic modalities (MacFarlane<br />

2005c). Joe asks Luca if their common friend Carlotta is in<br />

town. Luca knows that Carlotta is usually in town on<br />

Fridays, but hasn’t seen Carlotta since Wednesday. So, he<br />

answers quite confidently:<br />

(2) Yes, she might be in town.<br />

Then comes Holly, who informs Joe and Luca that<br />

Carlotta just took a flight for Toronto: her mother is not<br />

doing very well. So, the example goes, Luca says:<br />

(3) Oh, I was wrong: she can’t be in town.<br />

At time t0, Luca’s utterance is clearly true: Carlotta<br />

could be in town, as far as Luca knows. Moreover, since<br />

Carlotta usually is in town on Fridays, Luca is perfectly<br />

justified in asserting (2). Nevertheless, it seems, (2) turns<br />

out to be false as assessed from t1 – once Holly has<br />

informed Joe and Luca about Carlotta’s departure. Again,<br />

MacFarlane suggests, truth is to be conceived as relative<br />

not only to a context of utterance, but also to a context of<br />

assessment.<br />

Finally, consider the following classical contextualist<br />

example (MacFarlane 2005b). Joe is working in his office.<br />

He parked his car in the driveway, and therefore knows<br />

that his car is parked in the driveway. So the following<br />

holds:<br />

(4) Joe knows that the car is in the driveway.<br />

Call this context 1. Now consider whether – while<br />

he’s working in his office – Joe knows that his car has not<br />

been stolen. Of course not: someone might have stolen<br />

the car. Call this context 2. Does Joe still know – in context<br />

2 – that his car is in the driveway? If knowledge is closed<br />

under logical implication, the answer is negative. For, since<br />

knowledge that the car is in the garage implies knowledge<br />

that the car has not been stolen, and since Joe does not<br />

know that the car has not been stolen, it follows by modus<br />

tollens that Joe does not know that the car was in the<br />

driveway. So apparently we have further evidence for<br />

relative truth: (4) is true as assessed from context 1, but<br />

false as assessed from context 2.<br />

We are now in position to frame MacFarlane’s<br />

conception of relative truth:<br />

(RTF) ∀p(p’s truth is relative ↔ (it is possible that there<br />

be two context of assessment CA1 and CA2, such that an<br />

utterance of p is true as assessed from CA1 and not true<br />

as assessed from CA2) 1 ,<br />

where p ranges over propositional entities of some<br />

sort. If correct at all, MacFarlane’s analysis of future<br />

contingents, epistemic modalities and knowledge<br />

attributions offers some evidence for the right hand-side of<br />

(RTF). Since truth is relative, according to MacFarlane, if<br />

and only if (RTF) is satisfied by at least one proposition,<br />

relativism seems to follow: truth is to be thought as relative<br />

rather than absolute, and so much the worst for classical<br />

semantics. So far, so good?<br />

2. Relative truth, Belief and Assertion<br />

MacFarlane’s relativistic framework face at least two<br />

different kinds of objections. Let us start with the first.<br />

According to Gareth Evans (1985), relativistic conceptions<br />

of truth are at odds with the highly intuitive (and widely<br />

shared) thesis that<br />

(TAA) Truth is the aim of assertion.<br />

For how could we aim at truth if truth-values depend<br />

on a parameter – the context of assessment – that is<br />

clearly independent from the speaker’s context?<br />

MacFarlane’s reply is straightforward: (TAA) is not the real<br />

norm of assertion. Rather, MacFarlane suggests, truth is<br />

what we are committed to when we make our assertions.<br />

More precisely, speakers are committed to: (a) withdraw<br />

the assertion when it is shown to be false; (b) justify it<br />

when challenged; (c) accept responsibility for what is said.<br />

Since this latter norm is not incompatible with (RTF),<br />

Evans’ objection, according to MacFarlane, does not even<br />

apply to it.<br />

Here is a potential concern. MacFarlane subscribes<br />

to the standard account of belief, according to which<br />

beliefs aim at truth in the very strong sense that no<br />

propositional attitude that does not aim at truth can count<br />

as a belief (cf. MacFarlane 2005a). The troubles begin as<br />

soon as we realize that, according to (RTF), beliefs cannot<br />

aim at truth as relative anymore than assertion can. But<br />

1 Cf. Kölbel (2002), p. 102.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!