13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Did you do something wrong if you couldn’t have done otherwise?<br />

– Deontic act evaluation and some doubts concerning “ought<br />

implies can”<br />

Michael Kühler, University of Konstanz, Germany<br />

1. Introduction<br />

It seems to be plausible that if you can’t do otherwise than<br />

what you actually do, it would be unfair to charge you with<br />

wrongdoing. Despite the familiar ringing of the “Frankfurttype-examples”-bell,<br />

wrongdoing should not be confused<br />

with blameworthiness. In this paper I will solely be<br />

concerned with the question whether the ability to do<br />

otherwise, in conjunction with the principle “ought implies<br />

can” (OIC), might function as a necessary condition for<br />

deontic act evaluation, i.e. judging acts as wrong.<br />

Firstly, I will present some short examples along<br />

with contradictory intuitions concerning the deontic<br />

evaluation of the acts involved. To solve this contradiction,<br />

bringing in next OIC (including “can refrain”) will, however,<br />

lead to some general doubts concerning the validity of the<br />

principle itself. A concluding example eventually gives rise<br />

to an alternative view, resting on normative standards as<br />

the basis of deontic act evaluations, while abandoning<br />

OIC.<br />

Some further remarks concerning the restrictions of<br />

my question might be helpful: I will not be dealing with the<br />

intriguing question whether freedom of the will requires<br />

alternatives. The “can do” here only refers to freedom of<br />

action. A little example might help: Assume you stand at a<br />

crossroads and two ways seem to be open to you. After a<br />

little deliberating, given you have no choice but to move on<br />

in some direction, you choose the second way and go<br />

ahead. Unknown to you, however, the first way is blocked.<br />

As it seems, you couldn’t have acted otherwise.<br />

Unfortunately for you, it turns out that the second way is<br />

the wrong way for you at all, given your goal to reach a<br />

certain spot in the landscape. It seems to be clear,<br />

however, that you indeed acted in choosing to take the<br />

second way, for you freely made that choice. But can your<br />

action be judged as wrong? One might hesitate to admit<br />

this, given the harmless situation. So let’s make things<br />

more grim. Assume acting freely in the only possible way<br />

means killing somebody. The question whether you did<br />

something wrong now seems to be more urgent. John<br />

Kekes (1984, 459f.) formulated a provoking example: A<br />

mentally ill sadist entraps people and tortures them to<br />

death. He is fully aware of what he’s doing and that people<br />

think of it as evil. However, it is also not in his power to<br />

refrain from doing it. Given the same inability to act<br />

otherwise as in the crossroads-example, might the sadist’s<br />

actions now be judged as wrong? One might be inclined to<br />

admit it, provoking a contradiction to one’s evaluation of<br />

the former action. Furthermore, if you have doubts over the<br />

ability of the sadist to act rationally at all, here is third<br />

example – less dramatic but maybe as deadly: The act of<br />

smoking might seemingly be a wrong act, given your goal<br />

of staying healthy, despite the fact that you assumingly<br />

cannot give up smoking. So the contradiction remains.<br />

What do we make of it?<br />

162<br />

2. “Ought implies can” and the ability to do<br />

otherwise<br />

Another familiar statement now might come to mind in order<br />

to solve the contradiction: OIC. You can only be required to<br />

do something if you are able to do it. If you are not able to do<br />

it, it can’t be required of you and, therefore, it can’t be wrong<br />

not to do it. It should be noted that Kekes formulated his<br />

example precisely in order to undermine OIC. Hence it is far<br />

from being accepted in general – indeed one of my central<br />

aims in this paper is to shed even more doubt on it.<br />

However, I will not go into every detail concerning the exact<br />

understanding and scope of OIC. For all my purposes here,<br />

it might be understood as semantic entailment or substantial<br />

moral principle. The “ought” of OIC will be taken primarily as<br />

the basis for deontic act evaluations. The question, then, is<br />

whether the ability to act otherwise, or at least refrain from<br />

doing something, is included in the “can”. The thesis would<br />

be: “wrong implies can and can refrain”.<br />

Ishtiyaque Haji (2002, 32f.) and Michael Zimmerman<br />

(1996, 88f.) explicitly argue in favour of this position. They<br />

take the following steps: First, they accept OIC. Second,<br />

some action can only be required if it is wrong not to perform<br />

it. This springs from the notion of “required” as “morally or<br />

prudentially necessary”. Third, conversely, if an action is<br />

wrong than its performance is forbidden which in turn means<br />

that agents are required to omit them. Fourth, given OIC, it<br />

follows that if agents are required not to perform an action<br />

then they can refrain from doing so. Therefore, the “can” in<br />

OIC includes “can refrain”. This, at last, also leads to the<br />

conclusion that an act cannot be wrong if the agent cannot<br />

refrain from doing it because it can’t be required of him to<br />

omit it. If one accepts OIC then the steps of the argument<br />

seem to be straightforward enough to count as valid. In the<br />

following I will refer to this position simply by OIC because,<br />

obviously, this is the core idea of it. Hence abandoning this<br />

position would also mean to abandon OIC.<br />

However, the presented conclusion seems to be<br />

clearly at odds with our intuitions concerning the mentioned<br />

examples. Surely, at least something is wrong with the<br />

actions of the sadist and the smoker. How could we<br />

reasonably abandon the claim that the sadist is required not<br />

to torture and kill and, therefore, acts wrongly in doing so?<br />

Analogously, should we see the act of smoking as allowed<br />

even in non-smoking areas just because a smoker can’t<br />

refrain from smoking? Furthermore, if I make myself unable<br />

not to carry out a required action it would follow that I no<br />

longer can act rightly. Michael Stocker (1971, 304f.)<br />

presents such an example – this time totally harmless again:<br />

I am required not to be at home in the evening in order to<br />

avoid disturbing party preparations. For this reason, I go into<br />

town and, thereby, make myself unable to be at home at the<br />

time in question. It follows that I can’t refrain from doing what<br />

is allegedly required of me. But that, in fact, would mean that<br />

it no longer can be required of me and I’m not doing<br />

something right in not being at home. However, normally we<br />

would say just the opposite. Being unable not to act as<br />

required would rather be regarded as fulfilment of my

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!