13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

kind of mythology (cf. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1975, §95). The use of<br />

the term ‘mythology’ reflects the fact that our world-picture<br />

cannot be justified or supported by argument, because it is<br />

what makes justifications and arguments possible: “But I<br />

did not get my picture of the world by satisfying myself of<br />

its correctness; nor do I have it because I am satisfied of<br />

its correctness. No: it is the inherited background against<br />

which I distinguish between true and false” (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

1975: §94). It must be stressed that what ultimately<br />

explains the fundamental role of certain propositions or<br />

beliefs is not, according to <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, an epistemic<br />

process or mechanism, but their intimate connection with<br />

our practices. It is the form of life that determines what<br />

must be taken for granted. As <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> puts it: “Giving<br />

grounds […] comes to an end; - but the end […] is our<br />

acting, which lies at bottom of the language-game”<br />

(<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1975: §204). By stressing the<br />

epistemological significance of world-pictures and forms of<br />

life as the necessary background of our epistemic<br />

processes and by calling the attention to the irreducible<br />

diversity of world-pictures and forms of life, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

seems again to open the door to relativism.<br />

Until now I have gathered signs of relativism in<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s thought. In the remaining of the text I will<br />

argue that his putative relativistic ideas are simply an<br />

expression of epistemological contextualism and that his<br />

contextualism should not be confused with relativism. In<br />

the first place, it is important to stress that, from a<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>ian standpoint, it is possible to accommodate<br />

the possibility of cross-cultural communication even in<br />

cases where the participants in the dialogue belong to<br />

quite different cultures. Languages owe their intelligibility<br />

to the practices with which they are interwoven and these<br />

practices may vary significantly from culture to culture, but<br />

mankind shares a common biological nature that<br />

constitutes the basis of our social or cultural practices.<br />

Therefore, it is reasonable to believe in the existence of<br />

commonalities in human behaviour that make it possible to<br />

understand other people; “The common behaviour of<br />

mankind is the system of reference by means of which we<br />

interpret an unknown language” (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1958, §206).<br />

In fact, at the level of intercultural communication we can<br />

rely on shared or similar practices as a basis for cultural<br />

dialogue. When the practices that we try to understand<br />

seem too remote from our culture, we can try to assimilate<br />

them through social training. Intercultural communication<br />

may face serious difficulties in the absence of a common<br />

background of practices, but it seems reasonable to think,<br />

in the light of the precedent considerations, that initial<br />

difficulties can be gradually overcome.<br />

Not only can we understand other cultures; we can<br />

also criticize them. To illustrate this point, we can quote the<br />

following passage of On Certainty, where <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

says that he would combat people who prefer an oracle to<br />

a physicist:<br />

609. […] Is it wrong for them to consult an oracle and be<br />

guided by it? – If we call this ‘wrong’ aren’t we using our<br />

language-game as a base from which to combat theirs?<br />

[…]<br />

612. I said I would ‘combat’ the other man, – but<br />

wouldn’t I give him reasons? Certainly; but how far do<br />

they go? At the end of reasons comes persuasion.<br />

(<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1975, 80-81)<br />

Since <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> claims that members of<br />

significantly different cultures cannot overcome their<br />

divergences and reach a consensus on the basis of<br />

reasons, it may seem, at first sight, that this passage<br />

320<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> and the Problem of Cultural Relativism - Rui Silva<br />

constitutes evidence for a relativistic interpretation of<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>. However, the metaphor of combat is<br />

incompatible with the permissiveness that is usually<br />

associated with relativism. Moreover, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s<br />

conception of cultural combat does not exclude rational<br />

arguments. He does not say that the presentation of<br />

reasons is useless in the context of drastic cultural<br />

differences; he only says that in these cases the power of<br />

rational arguments is limited and we have to resort<br />

ultimately to persuasion. We must note that, in opposition<br />

to what we would normally expect from a relativist,<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> does not resign himself to the diversity of<br />

opinions and cultures. In On Certainty, there is another<br />

related passage, where <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> mentions people who<br />

thought, in opposition to the science of his time, that it was<br />

possible (at that time) to get to the moon, and offers the<br />

following conclusion: “If we compare our system of<br />

knowledge with theirs then theirs is evidently the poorer<br />

one by far” (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1975, §286). Again, this is far<br />

from being a relativistic claim.<br />

The key for understanding <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s stance on<br />

cultural relativism is provided by the contextualist account<br />

of knowledge and justification that is developed in his later<br />

work, particularly in On Certainty. Like foundationalist<br />

theories of epistemic justification, contextualism accepts<br />

the existence of basic beliefs. However, unlike<br />

foundationalist epistemologies, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> does not<br />

conceive of basic beliefs as immediately justified or selfjustifying<br />

beliefs: “At the foundation of well-founded beliefs<br />

lies belief that is not founded” (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1975, §253).<br />

What gives basic beliefs their privileged status is the fact<br />

that they are vital presuppositions of our language-games<br />

and inquiries. The chains of reasons and justifications<br />

must come to an end, but the foundation of knowledge is,<br />

as we have seen, non-epistemic: it is our form of life, our<br />

social training, our practices. As a result, and again in<br />

opposition to traditional foundationalism, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

claims that what counts as a fundamental belief may vary<br />

from context to context.<br />

In spite of acknowledging that standards for justified<br />

belief are context-dependent, a contextualist is not<br />

condemned to relativism, because nothing prevents him or<br />

her from criticizing rival belief systems and even aspects of<br />

his or her world-picture. Standards of justification can be<br />

challenged and criticized both from the inside and the<br />

outside of a world-picture. In each particular context our<br />

critical reflection necessarily takes for granted some<br />

propositions, but these presuppositions of our inquiries are<br />

not, in principle, immune to challenge and rejection. The<br />

claim that justification is context-dependent does not entail<br />

relativism, but only that justification is an ongoing and<br />

open-ended process, always dependent on certain<br />

assumptions. If we consider, with Williams (2001, 225),<br />

that a relativist is a “disappointed foundationalist”, we can<br />

even say that contextualism is incompatible with relativism.<br />

To conclude, I would like to draw a parallel between<br />

Gadamer and <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, because the latter’s<br />

conception of understanding as a fusion of horizons can<br />

be considered a contextualist antidote against cultural<br />

relativism. In fact, and in accordance with epistemological<br />

contextualism, Gadamer claims that it is not possible to get<br />

outside our cultural horizon or inherited background of<br />

intelligibility, but instead of surrendering to relativism, he<br />

describes cross-cultural communication as a dialogic quest<br />

for truth that may well culminate in a correction of<br />

prejudices and in a transformation of horizons.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> does not mention explicitly the notion of<br />

fusion of horizons, but he could integrate it easily in his

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!