13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

2) ϕ( P ℑ ∪ Ρ ℑ )=ϕ( P ℑ ) ∪ ϕ( R ℑ )<br />

ϕ is therefore a Boolean isomorphism, i.e. a bijection<br />

between sets that preserve complement, union, and<br />

product.<br />

We further require that for each relation P ℑ there be:<br />

2.3) ϕ( P ℑ )≠∅ if and only if P ℑ ≠∅<br />

If two S-structures are Boolean isomorphic and<br />

satisfy 2.3) there exists a subset e(F) of the set of Sformulas<br />

such that, given two formulas F and G, there are<br />

satisfied the conditions:<br />

2.4) i) e(¬F) ⇔ ¬e(Fi)<br />

ii) e(F∨ G)⇔ e(F ) ∨ e(G)<br />

iii) e(∃x (Fx)) ⇔ ∃x e(Fx)<br />

iv) F⇒G if and only if e(F)⇒e(G).<br />

In particular let At ℑ 1...... At ℑ n, the formulas that<br />

appear as disjoint in the normal form of H 1<br />

ℑ and At ℜ 1......<br />

A ℜ n, and those that appear in the normal form of H 1<br />

ℜ,, and<br />

let us give the definition:<br />

2.5) Given a monadic S-signature for each S-formula F:<br />

e(F) ⇔∨{e(Ati)| Ati ∈ AtF}<br />

where:<br />

e(Ati)⇔Ati if and only if Ati∉{ At ℑ 1,..…,At ℑ n ,At ℜ 1,..…, At ℜ n<br />

};<br />

e(At ℜ i)⇔At ℑ i ;<br />

e(At ℑ i)⇔At ℜ i .<br />

The e(L) set of formulas so defined satisfies the<br />

conditions 2.4) i) -iv).<br />

Let us now consider the new signature S e ={e(Pi)|Pi<br />

∈S} generated by the images of primitive predicates in S<br />

and apply to it the usual definition of formula, generating<br />

the set L e of formulas having the following properties:<br />

2.6) i) the set of L e formulas coincides with that<br />

generated by S.<br />

ii) the set of atomic formulas generated by S e is different<br />

to that generated by S.<br />

iii) the set of sentences generated by S e is the same,<br />

modulo logical equivalence, as that generated by S.<br />

An immediate consequence of definition 2.5) is:<br />

2.7) i) e(H 1<br />

ℑ)⇔H 1<br />

ℜ<br />

ii) e(H 1<br />

ℜ)⇔H 1<br />

ℑ.<br />

So for every sentence G:<br />

2.8) H 1<br />

ℜ⇒G if and only if e(H 1<br />

ℑ )⇒ G;<br />

H 1<br />

ℑ⇒ G if and only if e(H 1<br />

ℜ )⇒ G .<br />

Let us now consider any primitive predicate Pi. We<br />

have, for 2.4) iv):<br />

2.9) i) H 1<br />

ℜ⇒Pix if and only if e(H 1<br />

ℜ)⇒e(Pix);<br />

ii) H 1<br />

ℑ⇒Pix if and only if e(H 1<br />

ℑ)⇒e(Pix).<br />

The Fraissè Theorem and Goodman’s Paradox - Tiziano Stradoni<br />

Hence e(H 1<br />

ℑ ) and H 1<br />

ℑ are satisfied by the same<br />

structure, as is e(H 1<br />

ℜ) and<br />

H 1<br />

ℜ . In particular:<br />

2.9) i) ℜ⇒ e(H 1<br />

ℜ);<br />

ii) ℑ⇒ e(H 1<br />

ℑ).<br />

We thus arrive at the conclusion that the two<br />

structures ℜ, ℑ are elementarily equivalent:<br />

2.10) For each sentence F: ℜ⇒F if and only if ℑ⇒F.<br />

Therefore ℑ≡ℜ.<br />

Proof:<br />

ℜ⇒F if and only if H 1<br />

ℜ ⇒F, for the theorem on<br />

disjunctive normal forms;<br />

H 1<br />

ℜ⇒ F if and only if e(H 1<br />

ℑ)⇒F, since H 1<br />

ℜ ⇔e(H 1<br />

ℑ );<br />

e(H 1<br />

ℑ)⇒F if and only if ℑ⇒F, for 2.9) and the theorem<br />

on normal disjunctive forms.<br />

By assumption 2.0) however, the two structures are<br />

neither finitely isomorphic nor isomorphic, contradicting the<br />

Fraissè theorem.<br />

More generally it can be demonstrated that:<br />

2.11) Two monadic f.o. structures are elementarily<br />

equivalent if and only if they are Boolean isomorphic.<br />

Finally we can introduce the following corollary:<br />

2.12) Given a monadic f.o. structure ℜ such that<br />

H 1<br />

ℜ⇒¬∃ x( H 0<br />

ix) for at least one H 0<br />

ix, always there is at<br />

least one structure elementarily equivalent but not<br />

isomorphic to it.<br />

3) An Application: the Goodman Paradox.<br />

For the sake of simplicity in this section we will only<br />

consider finite structures: in this case in fact isomorphism<br />

and finite isomorphism coincide and the Fraissè theorem is<br />

resolved by the assertion that two S-structures are<br />

elementarily equivalent if and only if they are isomorphic.<br />

Given the signature S={R,T} , let us consider the<br />

two structures not isomorphic between each other:<br />

3.0) Φ=<br />

3.1) Θ=<br />

are:<br />

The two Hintikka S-formulas satisfied by Φ and Θ<br />

3.2) H 1<br />

Φ⇔∃ x(Rx ∧Tx) ∧∃ x(Rx ∧¬Tx) ∧¬∃ x(¬Rx ∧Tx)<br />

∧¬∃ x(¬Rx ∧¬Tx)<br />

3.3) H 1<br />

Θ⇔∃ x(Rx ∧Tx) ∧¬∃ x(Rx ∧¬Tx) ∧¬∃ x(¬Rx ∧Tx)<br />

∧∃ x(¬Rx ∧¬Tx)<br />

Let us now consider an arbitrary 5 measure function<br />

μ(T, Ev) of inductive support offered by the evidence Ev to<br />

the generalisation T, such as to satisfy the following<br />

conditions:<br />

5 But in the Hintikka tradition: see [5]<br />

341

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!