13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Intercultural Dialogue in Philosophy … - René J. Campis C., Eduardo Bermúdez Barrera<br />

philosophy and finally to science, logic and exact<br />

disciplines.”<br />

As for Blanco, he admits being influenced by Kant:<br />

“My philosophical speculations started under the<br />

influence of Kant and neo-Kantians, without accepting<br />

that doctrine at all, but not knowing how to escape from<br />

it because of a lack of orientation in a purely commercial<br />

environment like Buenos Aires during the period<br />

1912/27.”<br />

After moving to Berlin in 1927, then he went to<br />

Vienna to study philosophy where he attended Schlick’s<br />

seminar (1929-1930. See Lindemann 1944, p. 146. Also<br />

Staedler 2001, p. 235). There they discussed Russell’s<br />

Analysis of matter and modern physics (the theory of<br />

relativity and quantum physics) as well as the foundations<br />

of mathematics. This coincides in time with the meetings of<br />

Schlick, Waismann and <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>. Having read in<br />

Buenos Aires the works of Poincaré –another coincidence<br />

with Blanco-, whose ideas he thought to be continued by<br />

the philosophy of the Vienna Circle, he soon found that<br />

“the only way out of the abysm of school philosophy was to<br />

apply the method of science to philosophy as well”.<br />

Despite his sympathy for the general positions of the<br />

Circle, he shows his critical distance with respect to<br />

Carnap’s early works (in our opinion, he must have<br />

referred to Psychologie in physikalischer Sprache):<br />

“… I realized that the weakest point of the Vienna Circle,<br />

and especially of Carnap’s point of view, was their<br />

position with respect to psychology that seemed simply<br />

ridiculous to me… Then I started studying psychology…<br />

My doctoral thesis was therefore, dedicated to the<br />

incorporation of psychology as it was practiced in<br />

psychological laboratories, with its diverse methods of<br />

research, to the system of radical empiricism, because<br />

Carnap’s behaviorism, constructed ad hoc for his logical<br />

reconstruction of the world, was not enough for me.”<br />

Finally, Lindemann published Weltgeschehen und<br />

Welterkenntnis in Viena in 1937. A review by Rudolf M.<br />

Rohrer was published in Kantstudien the same year. There<br />

is a reference to Lindemann and Quine having visited<br />

Brazil in 1944 (Dussel, 2003), motivated by the growing<br />

interest there in the works of Russell and logic. Lindemann<br />

also wrote a review of Quine in the Journal of Symbolic<br />

Logic (June 1948). Most of the information on Lindemann<br />

is supplied by himself in his article; other references are<br />

scarce, but this is enough to draw a partial portrait of the<br />

man and his works.<br />

III. Lindemann’s El Círculo de Viena y la<br />

filosofía científica and Blanco´s La filosofía<br />

en América: an intercultural dialogue<br />

In Buenos Aires Lindemann published an article at the<br />

Revista Minerva -a philosophical magazine (1944-1945)<br />

founded by young physicist and philosopher Mario Bunge-<br />

where he gives an account of the Vienna Circle and the<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> of the Tractatus. Then came Blanco’s reply. It<br />

contained many criticisms to the general positions of the<br />

circle. Blanco also expands antecedents provided by<br />

Lindemann. The latter refers to Vienna as an environment<br />

where liberal scientific and philosophical ideas had spread<br />

early.<br />

He gives a summary description of the Viennese tradition:<br />

assuming the contemporary trends in philosophy to be<br />

valid, he considers that<br />

“Instead of starting all over again on the base of new<br />

dogmatic metaphysical systems, we’ll obtain constant<br />

progress toward the elaboration of an adequate view of<br />

the world based upon the results of science.”<br />

It is interesting to see some of the points of<br />

convergence and divergence between Blanco y<br />

Lindemann, which will serve as guide to illustrate some<br />

historical ways in which intercultural dialogue between<br />

Europe and Latin America has taken place.<br />

As we have already seen, both authors started their<br />

philosophical speculations from a Kantian point of view,<br />

although not being completely in agreement with Kant.<br />

They also had in common the fact of having read authors<br />

such as Poincaré or Hans Vaihinger. These two authors<br />

moved in an intercultural context with a strong Spanish-<br />

German context.<br />

Both JEB and Lindemann were also related to<br />

commercial activities. It would be an interesting exercise to<br />

analyze this fact in the light of the ideas of Karl Kautsky on<br />

“Trade and Philosophy” in his Foundations of Christianity.<br />

The fact that both used to live in coastal cities is closely<br />

related to these ideas.<br />

On the other hand, both lived for a considerable<br />

time in Europe, an issue which explains the intercultural<br />

dialogue. While Argentina was built upon migrations,<br />

Colombia practically rejected foreign immigration with just<br />

few exceptions, Barranquilla being probably the most<br />

significant one.<br />

As to the differences between our two authors: they<br />

are represented by their intellectual and theoretical<br />

development, especially with respect to their positions on<br />

logic and metaphysics. Despite having some readings in<br />

common, Lindemann identified himself with the trend that<br />

moved towards the reduction of the importance of<br />

metaphysics, while Blanco got stuck in the tradition of<br />

metaphysical systems –those created by a single<br />

individual as his own representation of the world- because<br />

of his appraisal of Kant and Hegel, as we can see in the<br />

following quote:<br />

“It cannot be even dared to compare the logic that<br />

pleases the Vienna Circle by the mere fact of being<br />

innovative with the Critique of Pure Reason, not the<br />

work of a premature genius, but of a mature one… Kant<br />

had not been just satisfied with the sustentation of mere<br />

artificial combinations by means of arithmetical<br />

transpositions as the juvenile genius of Leibniz did, but<br />

with the deepening in the very essence of pure reason.<br />

With it he opened precisely the path of inner experience<br />

that was to prove fruitful with Hegel… Neither the ars<br />

combinatoria of Leibniz nor any of the newest logical<br />

artifices can be compared to Kant’s transcendental or<br />

Hegelian logic.”<br />

This marks a great contrast with Lindemann, who<br />

praised Leibniz, Frege and Russell. Lindemann knew<br />

already that<br />

“Any metaphysical use of logic, for instance, Hegel’s<br />

ontological logic and its derivatives like the logic of<br />

Croce cannot be sustained by any means.”<br />

61

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!