13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> and the Problem of Cultural Relativism<br />

Rui Silva, University of the Azores, Portugal<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> is frequently mentioned in discussions<br />

concerning the problem of relativism and interpreted either<br />

as a relativist or as an important source of inspiration for<br />

relativists. Unfortunately, relativism is an ill-defined<br />

concept, and this fact posess serious difficulties for an<br />

evaluation of <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s stance on relativism. Not only<br />

the general concept of relativism can be understood in<br />

different ways, but there are also different, although in<br />

some cases partially overlapping, varieties of relativism<br />

(moral, epistemic, ontological, conceptual or cultural<br />

relativism, for instance). As a matter of fact, one can be a<br />

relativist in a certain sense of the word and not in another;<br />

one can be a relativist, say, in the moral sphere and<br />

nonetheless reject epistemic relativism.<br />

Before answering the question “Is <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> a<br />

cultural relativist?” we need, therefore, to clarify the notion<br />

of relativism. Taken in its most radical sense, relativism is<br />

the thesis that all perspectives on a certain subject are<br />

equally valid or, alternatively, the thesis that all beliefs are<br />

equally good. We may wonder whether there are relativists<br />

in this strong sense. Since Plato’s Theaetetus the aforementioned<br />

thesis is considered self-refuting; in fact, we<br />

can infer from it that those who reject relativism are right…<br />

According to another, less radical definition, relativism is<br />

the view that values, truth or knowledge are relative to or<br />

dependent on a certain framework: a culture, a paradigm,<br />

a conceptual scheme or even a personal belief system.<br />

This is perhaps a more palatable version of relativism, but<br />

it is somehow vague and misleading, because, by<br />

emphasizing the idea of context-dependence, it seems to<br />

conflate relativism and contextualism. Such a conflation is<br />

undesirable; the fact that some key philosophical notions<br />

are context-dependent does not entail, per se, relativism.<br />

According to a contextualist theory of justification, for<br />

example, we justify our knowledge-claims by taking for<br />

granted a specific set of basic beliefs that can vary with the<br />

context. As a result, in different cultural or epistemic<br />

contexts our justification practices can lead to different<br />

conclusions, but a contextualist is free to criticize and<br />

reject rival perspectives. The mere idea of contextdependence<br />

is not enough to define relativism, because<br />

relativism, as the current use of this word clearly suggests,<br />

involves also a permissive stance regarding conflicting and<br />

even mutually exclusive perspectives or belief systems.<br />

Accordingly, it is reasonable to characterize relativism as<br />

the combination of the context-dependence thesis with the<br />

above mentioned permissive attitude. Because<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s epistemological contextualism is not<br />

committed to the permissiveness that is usually associated<br />

with relativism, it is possible, as I will try to show, to<br />

absolve him of the charge of relativism. Since I would like<br />

to focus on the significance of <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s reflections at<br />

the level of intercultural communication, I will privilege a<br />

particular branch of relativism: cultural relativism, i.e., the<br />

view that it is not possible for outsiders to evaluate and<br />

criticize values, practices and basic beliefs of significantly<br />

different cultures.<br />

There are some strands in <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s thought<br />

that apparently lead us to relativism. At the level of<br />

philosophy of language, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s later thought is<br />

based on two fundamental assumptions. On the one hand,<br />

there is the idea that meanings, far from being entities<br />

existing independently of linguistic use, are determined or<br />

even generated by use. On the other hand, <strong>Wittgenstein</strong><br />

stresses that sentences or utterances are intelligible only<br />

against the background of the non-linguistic activities into<br />

which they are woven. He coins the pivotal notion of<br />

language game to stress this essential connection<br />

between linguistic and non-linguistic activities: “Here the<br />

term ‘language game’ is meant to bring to prominence the<br />

fact that the speaking of language is part of an activity, or<br />

a form of life” (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1958, §23). In its turn, a form<br />

of life can be described as the totality of the practices,<br />

institutions and customs that constitute the medium of our<br />

everyday life. Considering that the practical and cultural<br />

contexts in which language is inevitably embedded can<br />

vary in quite significant ways, and since there is not a<br />

standpoint outside the plurality of language-games and<br />

forms of life from which we could evaluate them, the notion<br />

of language game seems to favour relativistic<br />

interpretations. It presupposes apparently, as Habermas<br />

(1988, 143) put it, a “monadology of language games”,<br />

each of them governed by its own standards or rules.<br />

Another aspect of <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s philosophy of language<br />

that may be invoked on behalf of relativistic interpretations<br />

of his work is the thesis of the arbitrariness of grammar. A<br />

grammar is, in its <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>ian sense, the set of rules<br />

that govern the use of linguistic expressions and determine<br />

the bounds of sense, affecting, therefore, our description<br />

and representation of reality. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> argues that<br />

grammar is arbitrary because, on the one hand, different<br />

grammars are characterized by different conceptual<br />

resources and alternative forms of representation and, on<br />

the other hand, it is not possible to confront grammatical<br />

frameworks with a non-linguistic reality; any attempt to<br />

promote such a confrontation would have to presuppose a<br />

language. As a result, instead of merely being the mirror of<br />

an intrinsic structure of the world, language contributes<br />

decisively to the constitution of the objects of our<br />

experience: “Essence is expressed by grammar”;<br />

“Grammar tells what kind of object anything is”<br />

(<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1958: §371 and §373). Equally relevant to<br />

the problem of relativism are <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s reflections on<br />

rule-following, because they stress the social and<br />

pragmatic dimension of rule-guided processes. One of the<br />

main results of these reflections consists in the claim that<br />

rules are not transcendent to the practices that embody<br />

them and that to obey a rule is to master a practice<br />

through a process of social training. Since speaking a<br />

language is a rule-guided activity, if we want to understand<br />

members of other cultural or linguistic communities, we<br />

must be acquainted with the practices underlying their<br />

linguistic behaviour; understanding others involves an<br />

agreement in form of life (cf. <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1958, §241).<br />

From this perspective, the absence of shared practices<br />

between different communities endangers seriously the<br />

prospects for intercultural communication and,<br />

consequently, for a critical evaluation of other worldviews.<br />

Such breakdowns of communication may well induce a<br />

relativistic attitude.<br />

We can also find in <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s epistemological<br />

reflections some themes that point, at first sight, to<br />

relativism. In On Certainty, in the context of a careful<br />

analysis of the basic certainties that sustain our practices<br />

and everyday life, he points out that these certainties<br />

constitute a particular world-picture (Weltbild) or even a<br />

319

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!