13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

In modern chess we find many examples of players<br />

who have applied theories that illustrate the concept of<br />

logical multiplicity of rules as,for instance Bent Larsen and<br />

David Bronstein. Let’s illustrate this with a diagram:<br />

The rule that is broken here is that there shall not be<br />

many moves made with pawns during the opening, but in<br />

this case it is perfectly justified by a strategy of restriction<br />

that is fully appropriate for the position. It reminds us of the<br />

notion of rule-independence as described by the<br />

theoretician John Watson (1998). Let’s take a closer look<br />

at this definition:<br />

“Many changes have taken place in modern chess, for<br />

instance, with respect to new ideas about the<br />

weaknesses, the relative strength of the minor pieces,<br />

the value of exchange and considerations on time and<br />

mobility. But the predecessor, and to some extent the<br />

precursor of those changes has been a certain<br />

philosophical concept so deeply embodied in us today<br />

that we almost do not even notice it. I call it the ‘ruleindependence<br />

concept’… It is simply the dispossessing,<br />

made by chess players, of the manifold generalities,<br />

rules and abstract principles that directed classic chess<br />

and still do prevail on our text books. Furthermore, the<br />

rejection of the very concept of ‘rule’ has been taking<br />

place in favor of a pragmatic research of particular game<br />

situations. The intense study of a large amount of game<br />

positions combined with a dramatic growth of playing<br />

frequency by the majority of professional players has led<br />

to a new way of looking at chess knowledge. This way of<br />

looking at it could be described in terms of ‘unconscious<br />

principles’ or also subtle clues that cannot be verbally<br />

expressed, that are continuously modified and measured<br />

to refine the judgment of the diverse positions. A ‘sense’<br />

has been developed for positional chess… [that]<br />

abandons (completely or to a great extent) the dogma.<br />

This is rule-independence.”<br />

The above diagrams are taken from an actual chess game.<br />

They show rule-independence in the sense of classic<br />

chess: the rule that the knights should be moved towards<br />

the center of the chessboard. The diagrams show that<br />

both white knights move towards the sides of the board.<br />

Technical analysis proves that it is the right strategy<br />

independent of what the so-called “classic rules” tell us.<br />

We can confidently say that in contemporary chess there<br />

are thousands of examples that confirm the ruleindependence<br />

concept.<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>, Language and Chess - Eduardo Bermúdez Barrera<br />

But what is it that allows us to relate Watson’s<br />

concept of rule-independence to <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s concept of<br />

logical multiplicity of the rules? We shall turn to the<br />

propositions of what is known as Hypermodern School and<br />

thus, to Reti- The goal of the school was “not to consider<br />

each position in accordance to a general law, but rather<br />

according to the principle inherent to the positions.”<br />

Let us revise three quotes (<strong>Wittgenstein</strong> 1992 and<br />

Waismann 1973) to illustrate this idea:<br />

“Wir reden von dem räumlichen und zeitlichen<br />

Phänomen der Sprache; nicht von einem unräumlichen<br />

und unzeitlichen Unding. Aber wir reden von ihr so, wie<br />

von den Figuren des Schachspiels, indem wir<br />

Spielregeln für sie angeben, nicht ihre physikalischen<br />

eigenschaften beschreiben. Die Frage »was ist ein<br />

Wort« ist analog der »was ist eine Schachfigur (etwa der<br />

Schachkönig).«“<br />

“[…] The game of chess does not consist of moving<br />

wooden pieces… The essence of chess is not the<br />

wooden figures. What is characteristic of chess is the<br />

logical multiplicity of the rules…”<br />

“[…] It does not matter what the aspect of a pawn is,<br />

because the set of rules of the game is what gives its<br />

logical place to the pawn. The pawn is a variable, as the<br />

x is in logic.”<br />

My suggestion is to integrate Watson’s concept of<br />

rule-independence in <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s concept of logical<br />

multiplicity. I included long quotes from current chess<br />

theory to suggest that the notion of logical multiplicity (as<br />

understood and applied by <strong>Wittgenstein</strong> as an analogy for<br />

arithmetic and grammatical rules) is well oriented. This<br />

analysis has proven Moore to be wrong, for no skilled<br />

chess player takes rules to be only the legal movements of<br />

the pieces, but rather also includes in his understanding of<br />

the concept the rules of strategy. Chess constituted an<br />

unbeatable analogy for his intuition of what grammar rules<br />

really are. Basic knowledge of chess strategy is advisable<br />

for those interested in developing a deeper understanding<br />

of <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s theory of language.<br />

“Now language is the work of thought: and hence all that<br />

is expressed in language must be general. What I only<br />

mean or suppose is mine: it belongs to me -- this<br />

particular individual. But language expresses nothing but<br />

generalities; and so I cannot say what I merely mean.”<br />

With respect to these words taken from Hegel 1991,<br />

I shall say that current chess theory confirms the richness<br />

of <strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s use of the analogy of chess. Many of<br />

<strong>Wittgenstein</strong>’s notions of language do say much more than<br />

he actually wanted to say when he used the analogy. His<br />

intention was rather to show concepts that couldn’t be<br />

adequately expressed by means of articulated language.<br />

And that is why he used analogies for grammatical rules<br />

and games rules. Finally, the analogy of chess has<br />

perhaps its limitations, but an analysis of them is a task for<br />

a different stage of the research on this topic.<br />

31

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!