13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Towards an Intercultural Phenomenology? – Objectivity,<br />

Subjectivity and the Constitution of Otherness<br />

Eva Schwarz, University of Graz, Austria<br />

I<br />

Husserlian phenomenology mainly deals with the relation<br />

between world and subject. Thus, transcendental<br />

phenomenology is concerned with the conditions of the<br />

possibility of any reference to the world. The methodical<br />

operation of the phenomenological reduction brings to the<br />

fore the transcendental structures which are already<br />

effective, but nevertheless non-thematic in the natural<br />

attitude.<br />

Even if we accept the methodological considerations<br />

so far, 1 one could ask whether there are not serious<br />

problems with regard to the topic of intersubjectivity in<br />

general and the topic of interculturality in particular. It has<br />

repeatedly been objected that Husserlian phenomenology<br />

has to be regarded as a quasi-solipsism which cannot do<br />

justice to the experiential fact of intersubjectivity at all (Apel<br />

1973, 83). Against this, I want to argue the following:<br />

Certainly, the performance of the reduction entails a<br />

restriction to the sphere of immanence. This, however, has<br />

to be seen as a purely methodical operation which implies<br />

no ontological consequences whatsoever. To put the world<br />

into brackets simply means to put the validity of the world<br />

out of action. This implies that after the reduction the<br />

negation or even the questioning of the world becomes an<br />

impossibility for the phenomenologist. Thus, in her<br />

analysis, she is neither – as objected – restricted to an<br />

inner sphere of privacy (introspection), nor to a mere<br />

description of “absolute” giveness. Rather – as Husserl<br />

has extensively discussed in three volumes of the<br />

“Husserliana” and in the fifth Cartesian meditation – the<br />

performance of the reduction reveals the close relationship<br />

between subjective and intersubjective constitution. In<br />

order to support this, Husserl suggests the thought<br />

experiment of the primordial reduction (Husserl 1950, 124<br />

ff): To perform this thought experiment means to remove<br />

from one’s experience all that which refers to other egos.<br />

This means to critically reflect upon all experiential<br />

phenomena which transcend the purely subjective<br />

constitution with regard to their intentional content. To put<br />

it differently: Obviously we are able to mark certain<br />

phenomena as objectively given in opposition to others.<br />

But every time we mark something as “objectively given”,<br />

the intentional content of “objectivity” entails the necessity<br />

of intersubjective reference and constitution. Therefore<br />

Husserl eventually came to the result that transcendental<br />

subjectivity in its full complexity is transcendental<br />

intersubjectivity (Husserl 1959, 129).<br />

Another line of critique was articulated from within<br />

the phenomenological movement itself: Even if it is<br />

possible to account for the importance of intersubjectivity<br />

on a theoretical level, one could wonder whether it is<br />

possible to do justice to this topic on the level of facticity,<br />

i.e., on the level of the concrete encounter with the Other.<br />

Does – as objected for example by Maurice Merleau-Ponty<br />

in his lecture about Husserl’s “Origins of Geometry”<br />

(Merleau-Ponty 2002) – phenomenology run the risk of<br />

falling prey to unjustified idealizations in performing the<br />

1 For further clarifications of the methodological prerequisites of this essay cf.<br />

the essay of Harald A. Wiltsche in this volume.<br />

308<br />

reduction? Is this seemingly abstract account of<br />

intersubjectivity even a violation of the phenomenological<br />

maxim “to the things themselves”? Does this – if it is the<br />

case – endanger the possibility of an “intercultural<br />

phenomenology”? 2<br />

II<br />

If one asks for an “application” of transcendental<br />

phenomenology to “concrete” problems of interculturality,<br />

one has to define the concept of concreteness to which<br />

one is referring. The problem of the Other as it is posed by<br />

phenomenology is a genuine philosophical issue. Under<br />

normal circumstances we trust in our ability to recognise<br />

the Other as an Other, without ever reflecting upon this.<br />

However, there are deviant situations which motivate a<br />

certain “breach” of this tacit confidence: Consider the<br />

extreme example of a comatose patient but also the<br />

encounter with a culturally different Other whose reactions<br />

possibly do not meet our expectations. Situations like<br />

these can motivate a certain change of attitude which can<br />

be regarded as a “mundane prototype” of the<br />

phenomenological reduction (Husserl 1954, 141 ff). We<br />

could start wondering how an Other is given to us under<br />

normal circumstances. Furthermore, we could start asking<br />

what the difference between “normal” and “deviant”<br />

situations exactly is and how our tacit confidence in the<br />

possibility of “normal” understanding could be justified at<br />

all. Thus, within the phenomenological attitude we<br />

suspend this tacit confidence (together with all other<br />

presuppositions of the natural attitude) and restrict<br />

ourselves to the modes in which the Other is given in direct<br />

intuition.<br />

To ask for the givenness of an Other means to ask<br />

for the constitution of an Other. Obviously, there is a<br />

remarkable difference between the constitution of an Other<br />

and for instance the constitution of physical objects. A<br />

coffee cup is always given in adumbrations, i.e., in an<br />

interplay of presence and absence. Similar to this, an<br />

Other is also given in time and space, i.e., certainly via her<br />

body she is given as a physical object. The coffee cup as<br />

well as the human body transcend every possible mode of<br />

subjective reference. Naturally, this is not the whole story:<br />

Whereas “givenness in adumbrations” in the case of the<br />

coffee cup means that we are always able to transfer every<br />

absent aspect into a present one (e.g. in changing our<br />

perspective or in manipulating the coffee cup), this is not<br />

the case with respect to all relevant dimensions of a<br />

concrete Other. So, how can we account for this dimension<br />

of the Other which is generally absent to us?<br />

One classical strategy do deal with the problem at<br />

hand is the “simulation theory of other minds” that provides<br />

us with an argument from analogy: One could argue that<br />

all which is directly given is the relation between my mental<br />

states and my corresponding bodily behaviour (e.g.<br />

2 Within this essay „intercultural phenomenology“ is understood as a<br />

transcendental meta-science that provides a reflective basis for certain<br />

empirical investigations. “Intercultural phenomenology” in this sense does not<br />

aim at mediating between different cultures but rather accounts for the<br />

conditions of possibility of reflection on intercultural dialogue as such (cf.<br />

Mohanty 2000; Orth 1984; Waldenfels 1998).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!