13.02.2013 Views

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

Preproceedings 2006 - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Towards an Intercultural Phenomenology? – Objectivity, Subjectivity and … - Eva Schwarz<br />

whenever I am in pain, I am crying; whenever I am happy<br />

to see my friend, I am smiling) on the one side and the<br />

bodily presence of the Other on the other side (Gordon<br />

1986; Heal 1986). As we can see, the relation between me<br />

and the Other is asymmetric: “Mental states” and<br />

“behaviour” on the one side, but only “behaviour” on the<br />

other. Therefore, why not infer that if there is behaviour<br />

then there have to be mental states too? Correspondingly,<br />

one could state, that whenever the Other is crying, it is<br />

possible to infer that the Other has to be in pain as well.<br />

However, this “argument from analogy” is highly<br />

problematic: First of all, we should critically ask whether<br />

this argument is a valid argument at all. If it were true that I<br />

had knowledge about the relation between my own mental<br />

states and my behaviour, what would that mean for the<br />

relation between me and the Other? Strictly speaking, if I<br />

could make a direct inference between my own mental<br />

states and my own bodily behaviour – which would seem<br />

to require already a third-person-perspective on my body –<br />

all I could infer is a relation between my mental states, my<br />

behaviour and the behaviour of the Other. I cannot see<br />

why this argument should provide us with an account of<br />

someone else’s mental states or – to say it differently –<br />

why the Other should not be a marionette of my own<br />

mental states (Zahavi 2005, 148 ff).<br />

Apart from these absurd formal consequences, from<br />

a phenomenological viewpoint one has to ask whether the<br />

fact of recognising an Other is a matter of inference at all:<br />

Is it really the case that there is a sharp distinction<br />

between my mental states and my bodily behaviour? After<br />

the phenomenological reduction was performed, certainly<br />

not. What is given in direct intuition are not “mental states”<br />

and “bodily behaviour”, but meaningful situations, actions<br />

and smiling friends. The distinction between “mental<br />

states” and “behaviour” is a theoretical one which has to<br />

be bracketed in order to gain the phenomenological<br />

attitude. Even more than that: Within the<br />

phenomenological attitude, the Other is not given to us as<br />

a “bodily mantle” which makes us wonder whether there<br />

are mental states “in it”. First and foremost, the Other is<br />

given to us as the intentional content “Other”, i.e. as my<br />

neighbour, my friend, the stranger from a foreign culture. In<br />

order to recognise an Other, the differentiation between<br />

“mental states” and “behaviour“ is misleading. It makes it<br />

impossible to recognize an Other as an “other Self”, by<br />

paving the way to the Other as an object. In encountering<br />

an Other we do not apply any knowledge about analogies<br />

and inferences. Otherwise, we could not explain for<br />

instance, why babies recognise their mother even at an<br />

age where one would not expect them to be in possession<br />

of theoretical concepts of that kind (Fuchs 2000, 275 ff).<br />

However, what is the scope of these<br />

phenomenological insights? One could critically ask<br />

whether phenomenology gives us better explanations than<br />

for instance the “argument from analogy”. Against such<br />

objections, one has to bear in mind that phenomenology<br />

does not aim at explanations of this kind at all. Rather,<br />

phenomenological analysis critically reflects upon the<br />

convictions, other theories already presuppose in<br />

formulating their questions and answers. To put it<br />

differently: Phenomenology helps us to limit the scope of<br />

meaningful scientific inquiry without transgressing the<br />

boundaries to positive science.<br />

III<br />

Consequently, a phenomenologist is concerned with an<br />

investigation of the intentional content “otherness”, in<br />

reflectively detaching herself from the involvement in<br />

concrete situations in which “otherness” appears (Husserl<br />

1959, 106-108). Thus, as a phenomenologist one is<br />

interested in the essential structures of intersubjective<br />

encounters: concrete encounters with Others may differ<br />

with respect to various aspects (e.g. the degree of cultural<br />

foreignness, the aspect of language etc.) but there have to<br />

be certain meaning-structures which allow us to recognise<br />

an Other as an Other. Maybe the most important insight of<br />

a phenomenological analysis is that the intentional content<br />

“Other” cannot be reduced to the constitutional abilities of<br />

the Ego, i.e. to my constitutional acts. First and foremost,<br />

the Other is constituted as constituting, i.e. as an acting,<br />

perceiving etc. alter Ego. Referring to the “argument from<br />

analogy”, the relation between Ego and alter Ego is indeed<br />

asymmetric, but in a very special sense. On the most basic<br />

level, it is no relation of knowledge versus inaccessibility,<br />

but rather of mutual constitution. In recognising the Other<br />

as an Other, I have to recognise myself as an Other for the<br />

Other.<br />

However, at first sight this may seem trivial. One<br />

could argue that the acceptance of this reciprocity does<br />

not help us in solving the urgent question of how to gain<br />

access to an Other. But from a phenomenological point of<br />

view this question is not only inadequate, it disguises the<br />

very phenomenon of otherness. To recognise the Other as<br />

an Other, i.e., to constitute the Other as constituting means<br />

to accept that I cannot have the experiences of the Other.<br />

Having the experiences of the Other would mean to be the<br />

Other. Seen from this viewpoint, the search for an access<br />

to something which is supposed to be behind the façade of<br />

otherness is to miss the genuine phenomenon of<br />

otherness.<br />

It is needless to say that this entails some important<br />

consequences for the question of interculturality: First of<br />

all, on this most basic level every Other is a “radical<br />

Other”, i.e., there are no “shades of otherness”. On the<br />

level of phenomenological investigation my neighbour is by<br />

no means less foreign than a tribesman I have never seen<br />

before. Certainly, this does not hold true for our every-day<br />

encounters: By birth we are embedded in an all-embracing<br />

horizon of language, of social, historical, personal and<br />

cultural structures. This horizon regulates the encounter<br />

with our neighbour much more effectively than the<br />

encounter with a tribesman. However, the scientific<br />

description of this horizon, the question of translatability<br />

etc. are empirical questions which do not lie within the<br />

scope of transcendental-phenomenological inquiry.<br />

Phenomenological investigation is concerned with the<br />

conditions of the possibility of such horizons; it is<br />

concerned with the relation between self, Other and world,<br />

i.e., with those structures which are always presupposed<br />

when we recognise someone as an Other within certain<br />

horizons and contexts.<br />

In following these methodological decisions,<br />

phenomenology takes up a position which can account for<br />

the fact of cultural relativity but escapes relativism. To<br />

account for the otherness of the Other means to accept<br />

the fact the no Other will ever be fully transparent to us. On<br />

the empirical level of description, translation and<br />

understanding there is always the possibility of error and<br />

refutation. But this does not lead us to a relativist position.<br />

In dealing with errors, refutations and misunderstandings<br />

we already presuppose a tacit level of transcendental<br />

structures which make it possible to even recognise<br />

309

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!