23.02.2014 Views

Shape

Shape

Shape

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

210 II Seeing How It Works<br />

First, there are the famous individuals of logic. <strong>Shape</strong>s are like them in important<br />

ways. In particular, both shapes and individuals can be divided into parts, now in one<br />

way and again in some other way, independent of any agreed formula. As a result,<br />

shapes, like individuals, aren’t like sets. Henry Leonard and Nelson Goodman clarify<br />

this difference. The following quotation strikes at the heart of the matter.<br />

The concept of an individual and that of a [set] may be regarded as different devices for distinguishing<br />

one segment of the total universe from all that remains. In both cases, the differentiated<br />

segment is potentially divisible, and may even be physically discontinuous. The difference in the<br />

concepts lies in this: that to conceive a segment as a whole or individual offers no suggestion as to<br />

what these subdivisions, if any, must be, whereas to conceive a segment as a [set] imposes a definite<br />

scheme of subdivision—into [subsets] and members.<br />

Embedding and the part relation are crucial. But the likeness between shapes and individuals<br />

fades as additional details are checked.<br />

The way shapes and individuals are used distinguishes them most of the time.<br />

Rules are applied to change shapes—in fact, I defined shapes and rules in concert to<br />

make sure that this was so—while individuals aren’t handled in this way. There’s no<br />

distinction between individuals and individuals in rules. This is difference enough<br />

when there’s calculating to do, but it may not seem decisive otherwise. And perhaps<br />

the contrast is simply a question of emphasis, with a common purpose. Individuals<br />

distinguish things in the total universe just as rules do in shapes. Only how? In the<br />

latter, it’s calculating with parts that vary as rules are tried. Though here, too, there<br />

are worthwhile shadings. Goodman and W. V. Quine set up the machinery—‘‘shape<br />

predicates’’—to calculate with ink marks (individuals) in a ‘‘nominalistic syntax.’’<br />

Marks and lines, etc., are much the same in terms of embedding and parts, yet neither<br />

relation is exploited. Instead, shape predicates are used to recognize symbols<br />

and texts largely in accordance with the rudimentary conventions of printing and<br />

reading—pretty much as described in part I. Predicates are framed to block ambiguity<br />

and to discourage my way of calculating with shapes. But this is no surprise—symbols<br />

and texts are supposed to stay the same in a syntax.<br />

Differences in definition are easier to compare. Individuals form a complete Boolean<br />

algebra that has the zero excised. The algebra may have atoms or not—it seems to,<br />

more often than not—and may be finite or infinite. Yet worries about zero—having<br />

something for nothing—pale against the possibility of taking infinite sums and products.<br />

I’m happy with zero (the empty shape) as an unremarkable technical device,<br />

because it makes a nice algebra and sticks to standard mathematical usage. And I’m<br />

unhappy with infinite operations, because I can’t figure out how to do them in a practical<br />

way I can understand, or to see the extent of the results in every case. Still, this<br />

isn’t all that’s different. Unlike shapes, there are no added operators for individuals—<br />

transformations aren’t defined. To be completely honest, though, the nonempty parts<br />

of any nonempty shape in an algebra U 0 j are possible individuals. But if j isn’t zero,<br />

then this isn’t so for all of the nonempty shapes in the algebra taken at once. <strong>Shape</strong>s<br />

only go together finitely. Maybe the real difference is that logicians and philosophers

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!