23.02.2014 Views

Shape

Shape

Shape

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

392 Notes to pp. 47–48<br />

1994), 221–235. Of additional interest, see L. March, ‘‘Architectonics of Proportion: A <strong>Shape</strong><br />

Grammatical Depiction of Classical Theory,’’ Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design 26<br />

(1999): 91–100, L. March, ‘‘Architectonics of Proportion: Historical and Mathematical Grounds,’’<br />

Environment and Planning B: Planning and Design 26 (1999): 447–454, and L. March, ‘‘Proportional<br />

Design in L. B. Alberti’s Tempio Malatestiano, Rimini,’’ arq 3 (1999): 259–269. March argues for<br />

geometry in design and against making it digital in computer models, echoing Fowler that Greek<br />

geometry wasn’t arithmetized. This fits nicely with shapes and rules.<br />

3. Christopher Alexander’s ‘‘pattern language’’ is meant for a Platonic world that’s divided once<br />

and for all. C. Alexander, The Timeless Way of Building (New York: Oxford University Press,<br />

1979), and see also note 6 below. Still, change is a staple of studio teaching in architecture, especially<br />

for digital architects who use parametric models and other computer tools in nonstandard<br />

praxis. This is about being poetic—<br />

[The] poetic act has no past, at least no recent past, in which its preparation and appearance [can] be followed.<br />

. . . [The] poetic image is essentially variational, and not, as in the case of the concept, constitutive.<br />

G. Bachelard, The Poetics of Space, trans. M. Jolas (Boston: Beacon Press, 1969), xi, xv. It’s hard to<br />

imagine a respectable design instructor who doesn’t know Bachelard’s phenomenology and rely<br />

on it in some way. But is the poetic image something to calculate? Variation is the business of<br />

parametric models. Nonetheless, they’re constitutive and imply a Platonic world—finite elements,<br />

etc. (constituents) are set in advance, that is to say, entirely in the past. This gives objective<br />

(combinatorial) results that block subjective experience. A lot is left out. I’m free to see and do<br />

more than my prior decisions allow. Constituents change—once shapes fuse, their immediate<br />

past is lost and I can divide them in any way I choose. The whole reason for shapes and rules is<br />

to make this kind of variation possible, so that calculating and seeing coincide. When I calculate<br />

with shapes, what happens now isn’t decided by the rules I’ve used (preparation), but depends on<br />

the rules I try (appearance). I can keep track of how shapes change in this process to define retrospective<br />

links between what I draw and what I see, but these relationships are never fixed. They’re<br />

reestablished afresh every time I apply a rule. There’s no concept for what I see and do, or anything<br />

permanent. What comes next doesn’t follow a definite sequence. The poetic act has no<br />

past—it’s always in the present. The poetic image is always something new.<br />

4. G. Stiny and J. Gips, ‘‘<strong>Shape</strong> Grammars and the Generative Specification of Painting and<br />

Sculpture,’’ in Information Processing ’71, ed. C. V. Frieman (Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1972),<br />

1460–1465. An early description of grammars for shapes (triangles) is in R. A. Kirsch, ‘‘Computer<br />

Implementation of English Text and Picture Patterns,’’ IEEE Transactions on Electronic Computers<br />

EC-13, 4 (1964): 363–376. Kirsch’s approach is unabashedly syntactic.<br />

5. J. Gips, <strong>Shape</strong> Grammars and Their Uses (Basel: Birkhauser, 1975).<br />

6. G. Stiny, Pictorial and Formal Aspects of <strong>Shape</strong> and <strong>Shape</strong> Grammars (Basel: Birkhauser, 1975).<br />

Here and also in G. Stiny, ‘‘Kindergarten Grammars: Designing with Froebel’s Building Gifts,’’<br />

Environment and Planning B 7 (1980): 409–462, I rely on vocabularies (alphabets) of shapes to<br />

define shape grammars and spatial relations, but not without showing that vocabularies fail<br />

when you calculate with what you see. The use of vocabularies of constituents or units to link calculating<br />

and design may seem contrived. Yet history proves otherwise, for example, for logic and<br />

architecture—‘‘Both enterprises sought to instantiate a modernism emphasizing what I will call<br />

‘transparent construction,’ a manifest building up from simple elements to all higher forms,’’<br />

P. Galison, ‘‘Aufbau/Bauhaus: Logical Positivism and Architectural Modernism,’’ Critical Inquiry 16<br />

(1990): 709–752. Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Tractatus is crucial to this, and it’s the model for Susanne

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!