23.02.2014 Views

Shape

Shape

Shape

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

38 Introduction: Tell Me All About It<br />

also have this spatial relation with respect to d, p, and q<br />

The arrangements are indistinguishable. Peirce would probably agree that my four figures<br />

are just like his two. Still, let’s look at some possible consequences—well, at least<br />

one. What happens to reading? Is everything from beb to qeq in the following table<br />

the same?<br />

beb deb peb qeb<br />

bed ded ped qed<br />

bep dep pep qep<br />

beq deq peq qeq<br />

No one thinks so. We’re not trained to. There’s the word bed to tell b and d apart, and<br />

p and q when bed is upside down. And surely, the alphabet doesn’t bother Peirce. He’s<br />

not worried about single letters, but about multiple objects and distinguishing arrangements<br />

that are the same. That makes the difference. But when are single letters not<br />

multiple strokes? What do arrangements of objects look like? Why aren’t they shapes<br />

with parts? Let’s see what I can say about Peirce’s figures when I test them in various<br />

ways.<br />

In figure 1, there are eleven horizontals and eleven verticals, while its twin figure<br />

2 contains fifteen horizontals and fifteen verticals. Four squares arranged in the following<br />

way<br />

on four adjacent points in figure 1 don’t look the same as four squares—or is it five?—<br />

arranged in like fashion

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!