23.02.2014 Views

Shape

Shape

Shape

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

88 I What Makes It Visual?<br />

But this doesn’t mean—as it did in Evans’s example—that triangles have to be<br />

described (represented) in three different ways for the identity to work in the way it’s<br />

supposed to. For the identity<br />

the embedding relation is given for lines, so that they can fuse and divide in any way<br />

whatsoever, but for Evans’s rule<br />

Three lines fi Triangle<br />

embedding requires that constituents—they neither fuse nor divide—match in an<br />

exact correspondence, as elements do in sets. Perhaps this is another way of seeing it.<br />

A shape—at least with lines, or basic elements that are planes or solids—is not a set.<br />

For points, shapes and sets coincide. Whether or not embedding is identity is key in<br />

saying how shapes work.<br />

My identity applies to shapes, not to their descriptions. As far as the identity is<br />

concerned, a triangle is whatever I draw. It’s simply this<br />

with no divisions of any kind—no sides, no angles, and no anything else. And it’s<br />

always there to see if it can be embedded. I only have to trace over it. Evans gets into<br />

trouble because of the way he calculates. He confuses a triangle—something sensible—<br />

with a solitary description—an abstract definition—that’s only one of many conceptual<br />

transformations. This is the kind of thing that can happen whenever my formula<br />

dimðelÞ ¼dimðemÞ isn’t satisfied, and in particular, when the embedding<br />

relation is zero dimensional and elements aren’t. <strong>Shape</strong>s and descriptions are different<br />

sorts of things. But more important, I can calculate with shapes without referring<br />

to their descriptions. This idea provides another useful way to think about visual<br />

calculating.<br />

Only before doing so, let’s look at Evans’s approach in a slightly different<br />

way. Let’s ask how to make it work, so that lowest-level constituents—points, lines, or<br />

whatever—correspond with what I see. They’re numerically distinct, and I can pick<br />

them out whenever I look. This shows more of what’s at stake—why lowest-level constituents<br />

are just another way of thinking about points.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!