23.02.2014 Views

Shape

Shape

Shape

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

55 Background<br />

and time. The way Euler came to describe polyhedra in terms of their vertices, edges,<br />

and faces—in terms of boundaries, boundaries of boundaries, etc.—is also enlightening.<br />

33 Peter Cromwell goes on to describe the tactile quality of these elements in the<br />

short quotation on page 32. 34 And Erwin Panofsky mentions Albrecht Dürer’s<br />

‘‘nets.’’ 35<br />

Euler and William Blake have the same politics. And Blake is a wonderful letter<br />

writer, too. His displeasure with ‘‘Newton’s Doctrine of Fluxions of an Atom’’ and his<br />

stirring vision of the ‘‘Republican’’ line were conveyed on 12 April 1827 to George<br />

Cumberland. 36<br />

The quotation from C. S. Peirce and the twin figures<br />

are from his famous article in Popular Science Monthly. It’s called ‘‘How to Make Our<br />

Ideas Clear.’’ 37 Ambiguity and clarity are opposites—it’s one or the other. One way to<br />

be clear is to see that figure 1 and figure 2 show the same arrangement of objects. Only<br />

how can I tell I’m looking at an arrangement and not at a shape? Maybe if I divide a<br />

shape into parts, it’s an arrangement of objects. But the shape comes first, and it’s there<br />

to divide anew when I look again. Evidently, arrangements like sets are ideas and can<br />

be clear, whereas shapes are ambiguous. What can be seen can’t be clear (unambiguous),<br />

and what’s clear can’t be seen (ambiguous). <strong>Shape</strong>s aren’t ideas. Was Plato right<br />

that philosophers make better rulers than ‘‘those who wander in the region of the<br />

many and variable’’? Is seeing mindless? Thinking with your eyes and dealing with<br />

ideas aren’t the same. And sure enough, Peirce shows why in his neat discussion of<br />

habit, after the passage I’ve cited. It’s another way to describe rules for calculating.<br />

What the habit is depends on when and how it causes us to act. As for the when, every stimulus to<br />

action is derived from perception; as for the how, every purpose of action is to produce some sensible<br />

result. 38<br />

The arrangements in Peirce’s figures are identical. But if perception is the test, then<br />

each supports different behavior. Is this a mistake? The philosopher finds ambiguity<br />

embarrassing and shuns it in logic and reasoning, even as the shape grammarist<br />

embraces ambiguity and exploits it in art and design. Rules are used in an open-ended<br />

process to decide when and how to change shapes with all of their ambiguity. It’s asking<br />

too much to ask for less, and this is true when less is more. Doesn’t anything hold<br />

still? One thing is clear. Arrangements like definitions and plans are mistakes—all four<br />

are made to check creative activity.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!