27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

104 SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS UP TO DESCARTES<br />

planets were conceived as attached or along which they moved. A causal and<br />

harmonious structure for the universe was also theologically supported, for a<br />

good Creator God would surely have proceeded according to a rational plan.<br />

This attitude clearly lay behind Copernicus’s criticism <strong>of</strong> astronomers in the<br />

Ptolemaic tradition for producing fine parts which could by no means be fitted<br />

together in a tidy fashion.<br />

It was with them exactly as if someone had taken from different places, in<br />

no way mutually corresponding, hands, feet, head and other members, all<br />

excellently depicted but not in relation to a single body, so that a monster<br />

was composed from them rather than a man. 17<br />

Copernicus’s own system as portrayed in the famous diagram included in<br />

Chapter 10 <strong>of</strong> Book I <strong>of</strong> the De revolutionibus (with an accompanying panegyric<br />

on the Sun) appears admirably simple and rational, but important cracks lie very<br />

near to the surface. In the first place the system was obviously physical<br />

nonsense. If the Earth is really moving with such huge speed, we should surely<br />

experience it by such phenomena as constant high winds and stones that refused<br />

to fall at the bottom <strong>of</strong> the towers from which they are dropped; also its whole<br />

body should fly apart, like the materials on a potter’s wheel that is spun too fast.<br />

Copernicus was not blind to such objections, and answered them in summary<br />

fashion, but in terms which we may find easier to accept than did his own<br />

contemporaries. And after all, was it worth destroying important foundations <strong>of</strong><br />

the well-tried edifice <strong>of</strong> Aristotelian physics at the behest <strong>of</strong> a mere astronomer?<br />

All this relates to Book I <strong>of</strong> the De revolutionibus, understandably the only part<br />

that is read by more than a few specialists in mathematical astronomy. But the<br />

later five books destroy most <strong>of</strong> the simplicity <strong>of</strong> this book in order to make the<br />

system work, that is, to ‘save the phenomena’, or provide a relatively good<br />

predictive device for planetary positions, for in doing this Copernicus, although<br />

rejecting the equant point, retained most <strong>of</strong> the techniques <strong>of</strong> earlier astronomy<br />

for explaining the planetary movements by combinations <strong>of</strong> circular motions, and<br />

in so doing produced a system that was arguably as complicated as Ptolemy’s.<br />

This was not arrant conservatism but a natural use <strong>of</strong> procedures with which he<br />

had been brought up, and which if rejected would almost certainly have<br />

prevented him from doing any work worthy <strong>of</strong> serious astronomical recognition.<br />

With these points made, the result is not surprising. The book did not fall on<br />

dead ground, but neither did it win unconditional acclaim. Among the general<br />

public it was seen to propose a pleasing or unpleasing paradox, perhaps<br />

interesting for idle conversation, but only to be taken seriously by eccentrics or<br />

fanatics. For instance, even before the book was published, Luther remarked<br />

that,<br />

Whoever wants to be clever must agree with nothing that others esteem.<br />

He must do something <strong>of</strong> his own. This is what that fellow does who

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!